LECTURE №12
PEDAGOGICAL TECHNOLOGIES IN TEACHING ACTIVITIES.
Theme:Pedagogical Technologies in Teaching Activities.
The
student has knowledge and experience about education, instruction and teaching
methods; recognizes and understands the importance of social interaction in a
child's learning; has knowledge about a child's development and learning; is
consciously aware of the teacher's role in the learning process of child; has
an understanding of music therapy to help children with difficulties.
Technological
Pedagogical Content Knowledge (TPACK) is a framework to understand and describe
the kinds of knowledge needed by a teacher for effective pedagogical practice
in a technology enhanced learning environment. The idea of pedagogical content
knowledge (PCK) was first described by Lee Shulman (Shulman 1986) and TPACK builds on those core ideas through the inclusion of technology. Punya
Mishra, full professor, and Matthew J. Koehler,
associate professor, both at
The TPACK framework
argues that effective technology integration for teaching specific content or
subject matter requires understanding and negotiating the relationships between
these three components: Technology, Pedagogy, and Content. A teacher capable of
negotiating these relationships represents a form of expertise different from,
and (perhaps) broader than, the knowledge of a disciplinary expert (say a
scientist or a musician or sociologist), a technology expert (a computer
engineer) or an expert at teaching/pedagogy (an experienced educator).
The TPACK framework
highlights complex relationships that exist between content, pedagogy and
technology knowledge areas and may be a useful organizational structure for
defining what it is that teachers need to know to integrate technology
effectively (Archambault & Crippen,
2009).
Technology is
storming campuses across
The automobile
provides a good lesson. Early motorists were lured into the car market by the
promises of adventure and freedom through mobility. The folks selling us
vehicles for the information highway are promising an improved quality of life
and learning. To avoid atmospheric degradation and the techno-travellers' variation on gridlock, we need to take the time
to ask some serious questions.
Our teaching has a
history, too. Traditional pedagogical approaches emphasized the teacher as
knowledge broker and the student as receiver of knowledge. The work was about
content mastery. The "new" pedagogy - some refer to it as critical
pedagogy, others as social constructivism - emphasizes the student as learner
in a social context and knowledge as produced within a social context. This
student-centred pedagogy seems to have been more
thoroughly adopted at the elementary level where teachers are working to accommodate
individual differences and build social systems. It is our argument that the
pedagogy that characterizes much of the teaching at the post- secondary level
is presently inadequate for evaluating the opportunities and the dangers of
educational technology. Insights from student-centred
elementary contexts along with ground-breaking work with educational technology
at the post-secondary level provide the basis for our insistence that in
considering educational technology, pedagogical concerns and support for
professional development should receive top priority.
Technology in the
World - Promises and Paranoia
The introduction of
new technologies on a mass scale in North America has relied upon a widespread
and systematic marketing campaign, one that equates the adoption of new
technology with achievement (or increasingly, retention) of the "good
life", and ties the failure to adopt new technology with dire individual
and social consequences. Historically, a utopian vision has ushered in technological
change. It is not until we find ourselves virtually enslaved to it (Mander, 1991) cites the examples of the automobile and the
telephone) that we start to identify the wide range of implications, intended
and unintended, of its use. The same corporations are using the same marketing
plan to urge post-secondary educators to adopt educational technologies -
promises and paranoia. There are promises that inadequate pedagogy will be made
good by the technology; there is paranoia that without technology societal slippage
in international trade will continue, and lowered standards of living will be
the consequence for post-secondary graduates who will not have the skills
necessary for decent employment.
We are told that
North American economies are becoming less competitive internationally.
Declining trade advantages are supposedly behind the deficit and the
accompanying cuts in social spending. The "good life" is threatened.
The only way to revive it is through technological advances. Rising
unemployment is blamed on a lack of job related training, and computer skills
are portrayed as the means by which individuals can participate in the
technological revolution. For this economic revival, we are told we must
re-tool our educational institutions to produce a highly skilled workforce.
This marketing
strategy ignores the fact that jobless growth has been one consequence of new
technologies the introduction of which has been accompanied by the
globalization of capital, the internationalization of work, and the downsizing of
government.
Rather than
delivering the "good life," the impact of computer technology on the
economies of the industrialized world has been dehumanizing. Jeremy Rifkin
documents the grim story in his book, The End of Work - The Decline of the
Global Labor Force and the Dawn of the Post Market Era. Between 1989 and `93,
more than 1.8 million workers in the manufacturing sector in the
If you think these
workers have landed on their feet in new technologies jobs, or in the expanding
service sector, Rifkin suggests you think again. Of the 1.8 million displaced
manufacturing workers, one third found new jobs in service, but at a 20 per
cent drop in pay. These low-paying jobs are often part-time, and without
benefits. Guy Standing refers to the trend of replacing well-paying permanent
blue-collar jobs with poorly paying, part-time, temporary, service jobs as the
"feminization of labour" (Standing, 1989,
pp. 1077-1095). This change in the nature of work has enabled major corporations
to pay $22 million less in wages over the decade of the 1980s.
The jobs that
haven't been automated out of existence in the industrialized countries have
been moved out of reach of their incumbent workers moved off shore to poor
countries where poor wages and poor working conditions put more pressure on the
remaining workers in
Promises of the
"good life" via the computer revolution have not been realized for
most people. The winners of this revolution are referred to by Rifkin as
"the new cosmopolitans," as he records the fact that in 1953
executive compensation was 22 per cent of corporate profits; in 1987, 61 per
cent. In 1979 the CEO earned 20 times the wage of the average manufacturing
worker; in 1988, the CEO took home 93 times as many dollars as her/his
employee. And in some macabre sense of balance, the number of people living in
poverty has grown remarkably, too. In 1989, 31.5 million Americans lived in
poverty, in 1991 it was 35.78 million, in 1992, up to 36.9 million (Rifkin,
1995).
Technology has
definitely delivered on its promise of efficiency and productivity growth.
Market forces and globalization have turned these productivity gains into
handsome profits for a very small sector of society. We have to wonder what
substance lies behind the promises associated with emerging technologies in
education, and whether the distribution of advantage will be as uneven as it
has been in the manufacturing sector.
The silicon
snake-oil sellers (Stoll, 1995) do not draw to our attention the dangerous consequences
of technology. The same automobile that promised freedom and adventure has
fouled the neighbourhood, snarled our adventure with
congestion, threatened our supply of fossil fuels, made a mockery of
"rush" hour, and killed many of our citizens.
The naive view of
technology as value neutral has been challenged by scholars who have
demonstrated that technology is conceived and constructed within specific
social circumstances and has implications for social relations. Ursula Franklin
makes a distinction between holistic technologies and prescriptive
technologies, the former being technologies that enable egalitarian
relationships by their use, the latter being technologies that are founded on
hierarchical relationships.
Holistic
technologies are normally associated with the notion of craft. Artisans, be
they potters, weavers, metal- smiths, or cooks, control the process of their
own work from beginning to finish. (Franklin, 1990, p. 18)
In contrast,
prescriptive technologies entail a division of labour
whereby "the making or doing of something is broken down into clearly
identifiable steps" (Franklin, 1990, p. 24). A worker or group of workers
carries out each step in isolation from other workers performing different
steps. It is this very combination of the division of labour
and atomism of tasks that necessitates a supervisory relationship. The
distinction between prescriptive and holistic technologies is one between
control-related and work-related production processes.
If there ever was a
growth process, a process that cannot be divided into rigid predetermined
steps, it is education. (Franklin, 1990, p. 29)
Postman notes that
"the uses made of any technology are largely determined by the structure
of the technology itself... functions follow from its form" (Postman,
1993, p. 7). Encoded within the technology are criteria for social
relationships.
Just as technologies, or specific uses of technologies can separate
bosses from workers, they can create insiders and outsiders in other ways.
Rifkin's data speaks to the winners and losers of the technologically
restructured economy. Postman identifies the insiders who "can do"
when he observes, "those who cultivate competence in the use of a new
technology become an elite group that are granted undeserved authority and
prestige by those who have no such competence" (Postman, 1993, p. 9).
Insider and outsider status along gender lines is documented by Wajcman who notes, "As with science, the very language
of technology, its symbolism, is masculine" (Wajcman,
1991, p. 156). The earliest contacts children have with computers leave a masculinist imprint - from the home-computer usually
purchased for the boys in the family to the harassment of girls in schools by
boys monopolizing computers, from the war-game based video games and software
culture to the association of computing with mathematics rather than language.
Girls are either denied access to this sphere or not encouraged to become
involved in it the way that (especially middle-class) boys are (Hickling-Hudson, 1992, pp. 1-21). In the world of work, the
kind of contact women have with computers tends to reinforce women's
marginalization. Computer technology reflects and reinforces existing relations
of power in society.
Postman has special
concerns about the impact that technology in the classroom can have on social
relationships.
In introducing the
personal computer to the classroom, we shall be breaking a four-hundred-year-old
truce between the gregariousness and openness fostered by orality
and the introspection and isolation fostered by the printed word. Orality stresses group learning, cooperation, and a sense
of social responsibility ... Now comes the computer, carrying anew the banner
of private learning and individual problem-solving. Will the widespread use of
computers in the classroom defeat once and for all the claims of communal
speech? (Postman, 1993, p. 17)
Educational
Computing: Elementary Insights
The promise and
paranoia of technology in society are duplicated in our schools, with zealots
guaranteeing educational transformation, and critics warning of the development
of a generation of antisocial nerds. If technology has earned mixed reviews in
society, what is its school report card?
The Apple
Classrooms of Tomorrow (ACOT) project in the
At the post
secondary level, too, researchers are cautious about crediting technology with
educational improvement. Schierman and Jones
acknowledge that there is an assumption that technology is de facto beneficial
to educational endeavors. However, they conclude from comprehensive, large-scale
analyses of reports of benefit (e.g. Wilkenson 1980;
Clark 1983) "that claims of large gains in achievement are not warranted
and, indeed, that the attribution of measurable gains in achievement to the use
of any educational technology should be viewed with caution, since factors
other than those cited as the cause of achievement gains may be
responsible" (Schierman and Jones, 1996, p. 65).
Nonetheless, the
technology has its champions who say that achievements online are equal or
superior to those generated in face-to-face situations (Harasim
et al, 1996, p. 27). Harasim and her colleagues argue
that the primary goals of the virtual classroom are to improve both the access
to educational opportunities, and the quality of the educational process
itself. They claim that in the majority of cases, these goals were achieved (Harasim et al, 1996, p. 88).
Furthermore, they
argue that, "Active learning is a major outcome of learning networks"
(Harasim et al, 1996, p. 29). Indeed, they seem to
claim that because of technology, learning environments are more democratic,
teachers and students are more respectful of group knowledge, interaction is increased, and is of better quality (Harasim et al, 1996, p. 28).
Chris Dede is another who extols the virtues of virtual education
claiming that,
The innovative
pedagogies empowered by these emerging media, messages, and experiences make
possible an evolution ...into an alternative instructional paradigm:
distributed learning. In particular, advances in computer- supported
collaborative learning, multi-media/hypermedia, and experiential simulation
offer the potential to create shared 'learning-through-doing environments'
available any place and any time. (Dede, 1996, p. 4)
Why Bother?
The implications of
the technology are complex, the jury is not yet in on
the benefits. As busy educators, from Kindergarten to post-secondary levels,
the choices about technology in our classrooms are troublesome. We could ignore
it, committing ourselves to the classical tradition. We could leap on the
bandwagon and hope we can determine where it is going. We could be fatalistic,
acknowledging the inevitability of the technological takeover of our social and
intellectual lives and admitting to our own powerlessness in the face of it. We
could engage critically, applying our own skills of scholarship and accepting
the responsibility for advocacy that accompanies our chosen profession.
Assuming that
technology will not be absent from the future of the students we teach, we
support Penley and Ross's call for the creation of a technoliterate critical mass. While acknowledging that
"the odds are firmly stacked against the efforts of those committed to
creating technological countercultures," they argue that there is a
"pressing need for more, rather than less, technoliteracy
- a crucial requirement not just for purposes of postmodern survival but also
for the task of decolonizing, demonopolizing, and
democratizing social communication" (Penley and
Ross, 1991). Technoliteracy is the work of the classroom.
Technology as
Trojan Horse
Post-secondary
institutions are experiencing their own "new economy" of competition,
shortages of resources, and drive for "market share" in the form of
recruitment of students and "increased productivity" of faculty. Technology
is promised as a solution to these campus problems, one that will reduce costs,
improve teaching, provide evidence of the "currency" of the
institution, and help graduates develop the job specific skills that will make
them employable in Rifkin's brave new world.
Technology, of
course, will not necessarily do any of these things. It does seem however, to
attract endowments and contributions from corporations, and it seems to be an
aspect of campus infrastructure that even cash-strapped institutions will
consider as an investment. It may also introduce enough tension and dissonance
in the traditional classroom as to provide opportunity for teachers and
students to examine the way they work together. There is some evidence that
when one change occurs, all things suddenly seem to be open to review.
In arguing that
technological change is ecological, says that
It is not possible
to contain the effects of a new technology to a limited sphere of human
activity...one significant change generates total change (Postman, 1993, p.
18).
Critical Engagement
With the Technology
The ACOT reviewers
reported that their project provided an opportunity to demonstrate how children
and schools could work differently. They described technology as an engaging
medium for student thought and collaboration, and claimed that the smart (our
emphasis) use of technology could increase student academic performance and
support the acquisition of a whole new set of twenty-first-century competencies
(Fisher et al, 1994, p. 29).
What is a smart use
of technology, and who are the smart users? Is Harasim
correct that active learning is an outcome of online education, or is online
learning only productive if it is active? Are teachers who use technology
smartly predisposed to democratic, collaborative, problem based pedagogy, or
does technology bring these behaviors into the classroom? Can we analyze the
impact of technology separate from the impact of teaching with technology? Does
improved student learning occur only when technology is introduced along with
different teaching practices? What teaching practices are best suited to
maximizing the potential of technology to improve student learning? Or more
fundamentally, what teaching practices are best suited to improving student learning?
The attributes that
Harasim assigns to online learning can and do exist
in thriving non-wired classrooms, especially at the elementary level. A similar
set of attributes appears as the Principles of Learning established by the
Government of the
Learning requires
the active participation of the student
People learn in a
variety of ways and at different rates
Learning is both an
individual and a group process. (British Columbia Ministry of Education, 1993)
It is the expectation
of the government, at least theoretically, that in all classrooms learning will
be "purposive, reflective, negotiated, critical, complex, situation
driven, and engaged" (British Columbia Ministry of Education, 1993),
emerging technology or no emerging technology.
A closer look at Dede's 'technologically empowered' pedagogies reveals that
they are
analogical, case-based, learning-by-doing ... giving learners
constructivist experiences, facilitating comprehension and ability to
generalize ... structuring group dialogue and decision making, facilitating
collective activities. (Dede, 1996, p. 13)
While it may be
pointless to have a "what came first" debate about technology and
critical pedagogy, we must concede their interrelatedness. It is important to
focus our attention on what Fenstermacher calls the
"manner and method" (Fenstermacher, 1992),
or Postman the "metaphysical and mechanical" Postman, 1995) of
teaching. To fail to recognize, as Cuban says, "Our character as human
beings and how we teach become what we teach" (Cuban, 1992, p. 9) is to
concentrate on the carving tools while ignoring the sculptor.
Martin Haberman puts it bluntly, "No school can be better
than its teachers" (Haberman, 1995, p. 777). He
calls for teachers to know what they do and why they do it. The technology they
use is not neutral, nor is their pedagogy. The ACOT researchers found that
well-grounded teachers were positioned to make the most of new tools.
Classroom
innovators are often teachers who have strong beliefs about how students can learn, a passion for teaching, and some idea of how
technology can help everyone involved to do things a little better or a little
differently. (Fisher et al, 1994, p. 207)
And, ACOT
indicated, teachers made fundamental changes in their practice.
Over time, ACOT's design changed from computer saturation which
supported the existing knowledge transfer approach to learning, to the current
emphasis on routine access where technologies are used to support
collaborative, project-based knowledge construction. (Fisher et al, 1994, p.
268)
Experienced
designers of distance education programs at the post-secondary level concur
that good learning experiences for students are the result of careful
foresight.
We invite course
designers to foster the open-ended, collaborative, and reflective processes
that this medium can deliver, while still relying on conventional ISD models as
heuristics. Designers need to attend to both the role and the extent of online
activities to their total course, as well as seek a match among teacher,
learner, format and content. (Berg and Collins, 1996, p. 79)
Further, there are
specific teaching behaviors that seem to be influential at the Virtual U. Harasim says
a learner-centered (rather than teacher-centered) model
has been found as the best fit online. CMC is meant for the sharing and
building of ideas, information and skills among the participants to strengthen
knowledge building, integration and application of conceptual information. (Harasim et al, 1996, p. 24)
She devotes
considerable attention to the consequences of moving from teacher to
facilitator, identifying key behaviors that may or may not exist
"offline" but are considered essential to successful teaching online,
including setting the stage, monitoring and encouraging participation, forming
groups, assigning role responsibilities, moderating and facilitating group
processes, establishing norms and grading performance.
While Paulsen
acknowledges that "moderators [of computer conferences] will perceive their
role ... in light of their basic theories and philosophies toward
education," he cites the work of Mason, Forsyth and Brochet
in identifying "task roles and socioemotional
roles", "organizational, social and intellectual roles" or the
contribution of the moderator as "goal setter, discriminator, host, pace
setter, explainer, entertainer" to ensure a successful computer conference
(Paulsen, 1996, p. 83).
Rohfeld and Hiemstra, too, define
the electronic classroom as a place for collaborative learning. They return to
the "essence" of learning, plugged in or not.
Teaching through
discussion relies on a learner- centered approach, whether the participants
meet face to face or on the computer screen. It rests on principles of
collaborative learning and egalitarian relationships." (Rohfeld and Hiemstra, 1996, p.
91)
Because helping
learners take increasing control over personal learning is a goal for most
educational endeavors, computer-mediated conferencing can be supportive of such
fundamental educational values. (Rohfeld and Hiemstra, 1996, p. 102)
The preponderance
of references to student-centered learning, a democratic learning environment,
the shared construction of knowledge and the changing of teaching practices in
these reviews of the positive presence of technology on campus persuades us that technology and critical pedagogy have a
promising relationship. Still, the improvement of pedagogy is a good end in
itself, and critical pedagogy has a role larger than guiding learning online.
Critical Engagement
About the Technology
It is not enough
for educators to provide students with a map of the information highway. There
are critical questions to consider about highways in general, and how humans
travel through their environment.
Introducing new
technologies into our classrooms is an activity of great consequence, because,
like other technological change, it is the re-tooling of the social. Postman
reminds us that
New technologies
alter the structure of our interests: the things we think about. They alter the
character of our symbols: the things we think with. And they alter the nature
of community: the arena in which thoughts develop. (Postman, 1993, p. 20)
At the same time,
in urging us to avoid demonizing technology, Haraway
argues that the boundary between the "natural" and the
"artificial," i.e. the technological, is entirely political. She
points out that we fear the technology that is alien, while we welcome other
technology, such as the contact lens, the ball point pen, general anesthesia,
convincing ourselves that it is not "really" technology (Haraway, 1991). This confusion characterizes our failure to
view technology as social practice and hence in need of the same attention and
skepticism that would accompany say, a change in policy with respect to legal
drinking age. By recognizing technologies as social in origin and social in
consequence, we provide ourselves with a much needed critical foothold to
engage with the technology, and to engage about the technology.
Research and debate
in classrooms at all levels about the politics of technology should surround
any skill building technology curriculum.
The Politics of
Post-Secondary Teaching
What support is
there for post secondary educators to develop and nurture the beliefs and
skills of critical pedagogy that seem to undergird success with emerging
technologies? Kearsley argues " ... we are still
trying to employ 19th century pedagogical ideas in the 21st century.' ... A
vast conceptual gap exists between the kinds of technologically based learning
and teaching methods that Chris Dede is talking about
and those practiced in almost every classroom and training center. Never mind
whether suitable hardware and software is available to teachers and students to
carry out such endeavors (it is not). Wholly missing on the part of most
teachers is the knowledge of such methods, the opportunity to try out and
practice such methods, and the time to think through ways to change the
curriculum to incorporate these methods" (Kearsley,
1996, p. 57).
The Carnegie
Foundation for the Advancement of Teaching conducted a series of surveys with
5,000 faculty members in 1989 to clarify the status of the professoriate and to
provide a portrait of American higher education, including the balance between
teaching and research. The majority of these faculty reported that they
consider teaching to be a central mission of the university and a rewarding
activity but that the reward system of their institutions was heavily weighted
towards published research rather than effective teaching (Boyer, 1990). In a
subsequent study of the relative importance of teaching, research,
administration, and service in determining basic salary, involving more than
4,000 full-time, tenure-track faculty in four-year colleges and universities, James
Fairweather reports that teaching activities seldom
were rewarded. In some cases, time spent on teaching was negatively related to
salary. Results showed the dominance of a research-oriented faculty reward
structure for each type of institution regardless of professed mission. Reward
structures favouring good teaching are lacking even
in the four-year liberal arts colleges whose specific mission focuses on
undergraduate teaching. Boyer concludes that without significant changes in
institutional reward structure, teaching at the post-secondary level will not
improve appreciably.
Faculty preparation
in graduate school continues to offer very little or no instruction on how to
teach. Faculty continue to rely on the teaching
methods they have always used - this despite research documenting the need for
students to learn actively. More often than not the choice of instructional
method is a habitual one rather than a reasoned decision based on the
instructional objectives of the course and content for the day.... college
teachers teach pretty much as they were taught. (Weimer, 1990, p. xi)
Some institutions
have established a specific unit on campus to provide instructional support
resources. New hirings include more attention to
teaching record than in the past. Still the reward systems
remain fundamentally unchanged and does not contribute to an environment
hospitable for the Trojan horse of technology. Not only must teaching itself be
deemed important, but teaching itself must get serious attention. Once again,
the K-12 teachers offer good counsel that the introduction of new technologies
must be accompanied by a commitment to teacher development.
The ACOT projects
acknowledged that "Successful technology use implies both change of
underlying frameworks as well as the incorporation and appropriation of
technology benefits into classroom practices" (Fisher et al, 1996, p.
199). They point out that for innovative programs to be successful, training and
staff- development components should constitute approximately 30 to 40 percent
of the total effort. This effort should include:
structured observation of accomplished practice
reflection on and discussion of teaching and learning
hands-on, collaborative learning
curriculum project development
teacher teams and [administrator] participation
commitment to share with colleagues
follow-up support
support for accomplished teachers
iterative expansion plans (Fisher et al, 1996, p. 243).
Francis Oakley
notes that the appropriate use of technology requires organizational change. We
suggest that the very organizational change required for the appropriate use of
technology in educational contexts is the provision of supports for good
teaching. Without time and resources for professional development and without a
reward structure that responds to pedagogical development by faculty members,
educational technology will be hard pressed to deliver on any of its promises.
Really, Why Bother?
Critical pedagogy
facilitates the development of a language of critical discourse. If we use it
as a social force we may be able to foster a generation of technoliterate
skeptics, equipping our society to engage critically with both the content and
the consequences of new technologies. Support for this critical engagement is
an important contribution educators can make to efforts to trouble boundaries
between insiders and outsiders as society shifts and changes.
Elementary teachers
know that hungry children don't learn much beyond the immediate experience of
having their basic needs unmet. And yet school lunch programs are hotly
contested in school district and state politics. Educational settings mirror,
or at least are structured in relation to, the larger social context. The
politics of hunger and exclusion in the elementary context have their parallels
in post-secondary institutions where institutional practices have remained
virtually untouched through the post-war era.
However, recent
climate studies and challenges to the canon have revealed institutional
practices of discrimination. They, in turn have met with a backlash against
so-called political correctness. When considering educational technologies,
post- secondary educators need to confront the ways in which technologies are
likely to line up in the construction of boundaries between insiders and
outsiders on campus, and whether this system break will permit the re-tooling
of the social in a liberating way.
It might be that
educational technologies bring with them to campus the resources, time, and
attention that enable educators to engage critically about the social. It may
be that failure to engage critically will enable the emerging technologies to
entrench outsider educational and social practices. We see the technoliterate skeptic participating in critical dialogue
with her peers as the only person able to function as a citizen in the face of
these dilemmas. The role of the educator in modelling
this skepticism cannot be overemphasized. Yes, we really should bother.
Menzies refers to the information highway as a restructuring
agent (Menzies, 1996). The argument we've made in favour of engaging with educational technology can be
summarized rather bluntly: restructure or be restructured!
Pedagogics is a normative science with its own subject of
research. The historical development of pedagogical thought shows strong
relations with philosophical-anthropological principles and with
historical-cultural characteristics. Education today is confronted with, among
other things, postmodern developments in society ('Hauslosigkeit')
and a change in patterns of youth behavior (from a standard career to a chosen
career). For pedagogical analysis, a renewed appeal to reason is advocated. A
suitable method is the triadic-pedagogical analysis, which reflects on the
parent-child relation in connection with historical-cultural developments.
We can safely assume that everyone
is aware that children cannot be left to fend for themselves and that they
cannot become adult on their own. However, not everyone is convinced that the
process of growing up and gradually growing into society requires an on-going
pedagogic relationship based on more or less pronounced concepts of what it is
to be a civilized human being. "It can't be allowed!" people cry when
they hear that school children are carrying weapons and that they use them on a
regular basis. A father will say that his children need a "good
education" so that they can come to occupy a "good position" in
society. While a mother might say that as far as she is concerned, the most
important thing is that her children should be "honest" and that they
should learn to be prepared to help one another.
In all of these cases there is
clearly some notion of the relationship between education and the socio-cultural
environment, of the current state of society and society as it might be, of
what should be considered normal or abnormal in terms of human behavior and of
the kinds of things that education can strive towards. But not everyone is
willing to accept the practical pedagogic consequences that these notions imply
-- in other words, the need to maintain an on-going pedagogic relationship in
which educators care for the children in their charge, are aware of their
responsibility and are also ethically responsible, relating to the surrounding
culture critically and consciously and making every effort to enable children
to take part in society responsibly and effectively in their own way.
LECTURE №12 PEDAGOGICAL TECHNOLOGIES IN TEACHING ACTIVITIES. Theme:Pedagogical Technologies in Teaching Activities. The
student has knowledge and experience about education, instruction and teaching
methods; recognizes and understands the importance of social interaction in a
child's learning; has knowledge about a child's development and learning; is
consciously aware of the teacher's role in the learning process of child; has
an understanding of music therapy to help children with difficulties. Technological
Pedagogical Content Knowledge (TPACK) is a framework to understand and describe
the kinds of knowledge needed by a teacher for effective pedagogical practice
in a technology enhanced learning environment. The idea of pedagogical content
knowledge (PCK) was first described by Lee Shulman (Shulman 1986) and TPACK builds on those core ideas through the inclusion of technology. Punya
Mishra, full professor, and Matthew J. Koehler,
associate professor, both at The TPACK framework
argues that effective technology integration for teaching specific content or
subject matter requires understanding and negotiating the relationships between
these three components: Technology, Pedagogy, and Content. A teacher capable of
negotiating these relationships represents a form of expertise different from,
and (perhaps) broader than, the knowledge of a disciplinary expert (say a
scientist or a musician or sociologist), a technology expert (a computer
engineer) or an expert at teaching/pedagogy (an experienced educator). The TPACK framework
highlights complex relationships that exist between content, pedagogy and
technology knowledge areas and may be a useful organizational structure for
defining what it is that teachers need to know to integrate technology
effectively (Archambault & Crippen,
2009). Technology is
storming campuses across The automobile
provides a good lesson. Early motorists were lured into the car market by the
promises of adventure and freedom through mobility. The folks selling us
vehicles for the information highway are promising an improved quality of life
and learning. To avoid atmospheric degradation and the techno-travellers' variation on gridlock, we need to take the time
to ask some serious questions. Our teaching has a
history, too. Traditional pedagogical approaches emphasized the teacher as
knowledge broker and the student as receiver of knowledge. The work was about
content mastery. The "new" pedagogy - some refer to it as critical
pedagogy, others as social constructivism - emphasizes the student as learner
in a social context and knowledge as produced within a social context. This
student-centred pedagogy seems to have been more
thoroughly adopted at the elementary level where teachers are working to accommodate
individual differences and build social systems. It is our argument that the
pedagogy that characterizes much of the teaching at the post- secondary level
is presently inadequate for evaluating the opportunities and the dangers of
educational technology. Insights from student-centred
elementary contexts along with ground-breaking work with educational technology
at the post-secondary level provide the basis for our insistence that in
considering educational technology, pedagogical concerns and support for
professional development should receive top priority. Technology in the
World - Promises and Paranoia The introduction of
new technologies on a mass scale in North America has relied upon a widespread
and systematic marketing campaign, one that equates the adoption of new
technology with achievement (or increasingly, retention) of the "good
life", and ties the failure to adopt new technology with dire individual
and social consequences. Historically, a utopian vision has ushered in technological
change. It is not until we find ourselves virtually enslaved to it (Mander, 1991) cites the examples of the automobile and the
telephone) that we start to identify the wide range of implications, intended
and unintended, of its use. The same corporations are using the same marketing
plan to urge post-secondary educators to adopt educational technologies -
promises and paranoia. There are promises that inadequate pedagogy will be made
good by the technology; there is paranoia that without technology societal slippage
in international trade will continue, and lowered standards of living will be
the consequence for post-secondary graduates who will not have the skills
necessary for decent employment. We are told that
North American economies are becoming less competitive internationally.
Declining trade advantages are supposedly behind the deficit and the
accompanying cuts in social spending. The "good life" is threatened.
The only way to revive it is through technological advances. Rising
unemployment is blamed on a lack of job related training, and computer skills
are portrayed as the means by which individuals can participate in the
technological revolution. For this economic revival, we are told we must
re-tool our educational institutions to produce a highly skilled workforce. This marketing
strategy ignores the fact that jobless growth has been one consequence of new
technologies the introduction of which has been accompanied by the
globalization of capital, the internationalization of work, and the downsizing of
government. Rather than
delivering the "good life," the impact of computer technology on the
economies of the industrialized world has been dehumanizing. Jeremy Rifkin
documents the grim story in his book, The End of Work - The Decline of the
Global Labor Force and the Dawn of the Post Market Era. Between 1989 and `93,
more than 1.8 million workers in the manufacturing sector in the If you think these
workers have landed on their feet in new technologies jobs, or in the expanding
service sector, Rifkin suggests you think again. Of the 1.8 million displaced
manufacturing workers, one third found new jobs in service, but at a 20 per
cent drop in pay. These low-paying jobs are often part-time, and without
benefits. Guy Standing refers to the trend of replacing well-paying permanent
blue-collar jobs with poorly paying, part-time, temporary, service jobs as the
"feminization of labour" (Standing, 1989,
pp. 1077-1095). This change in the nature of work has enabled major corporations
to pay $22 million less in wages over the decade of the 1980s. The jobs that
haven't been automated out of existence in the industrialized countries have
been moved out of reach of their incumbent workers moved off shore to poor
countries where poor wages and poor working conditions put more pressure on the
remaining workers in Promises of the
"good life" via the computer revolution have not been realized for
most people. The winners of this revolution are referred to by Rifkin as
"the new cosmopolitans," as he records the fact that in 1953
executive compensation was 22 per cent of corporate profits; in 1987, 61 per
cent. In 1979 the CEO earned 20 times the wage of the average manufacturing
worker; in 1988, the CEO took home 93 times as many dollars as her/his
employee. And in some macabre sense of balance, the number of people living in
poverty has grown remarkably, too. In 1989, 31.5 million Americans lived in
poverty, in 1991 it was 35.78 million, in 1992, up to 36.9 million (Rifkin,
1995). Technology has
definitely delivered on its promise of efficiency and productivity growth.
Market forces and globalization have turned these productivity gains into
handsome profits for a very small sector of society. We have to wonder what
substance lies behind the promises associated with emerging technologies in
education, and whether the distribution of advantage will be as uneven as it
has been in the manufacturing sector. The silicon
snake-oil sellers (Stoll, 1995) do not draw to our attention the dangerous consequences
of technology. The same automobile that promised freedom and adventure has
fouled the neighbourhood, snarled our adventure with
congestion, threatened our supply of fossil fuels, made a mockery of
"rush" hour, and killed many of our citizens. The naive view of
technology as value neutral has been challenged by scholars who have
demonstrated that technology is conceived and constructed within specific
social circumstances and has implications for social relations. Ursula Franklin
makes a distinction between holistic technologies and prescriptive
technologies, the former being technologies that enable egalitarian
relationships by their use, the latter being technologies that are founded on
hierarchical relationships. Holistic
technologies are normally associated with the notion of craft. Artisans, be
they potters, weavers, metal- smiths, or cooks, control the process of their
own work from beginning to finish. (Franklin, 1990, p. 18) In contrast,
prescriptive technologies entail a division of labour
whereby "the making or doing of something is broken down into clearly
identifiable steps" (Franklin, 1990, p. 24). A worker or group of workers
carries out each step in isolation from other workers performing different
steps. It is this very combination of the division of labour
and atomism of tasks that necessitates a supervisory relationship. The
distinction between prescriptive and holistic technologies is one between
control-related and work-related production processes. If there ever was a
growth process, a process that cannot be divided into rigid predetermined
steps, it is education. (Franklin, 1990, p. 29) Postman notes that
"the uses made of any technology are largely determined by the structure
of the technology itself... functions follow from its form" (Postman,
1993, p. 7). Encoded within the technology are criteria for social
relationships. Just as technologies, or specific uses of technologies can separate
bosses from workers, they can create insiders and outsiders in other ways.
Rifkin's data speaks to the winners and losers of the technologically
restructured economy. Postman identifies the insiders who "can do"
when he observes, "those who cultivate competence in the use of a new
technology become an elite group that are granted undeserved authority and
prestige by those who have no such competence" (Postman, 1993, p. 9).
Insider and outsider status along gender lines is documented by Wajcman who notes, "As with science, the very language
of technology, its symbolism, is masculine" (Wajcman,
1991, p. 156). The earliest contacts children have with computers leave a masculinist imprint - from the home-computer usually
purchased for the boys in the family to the harassment of girls in schools by
boys monopolizing computers, from the war-game based video games and software
culture to the association of computing with mathematics rather than language.
Girls are either denied access to this sphere or not encouraged to become
involved in it the way that (especially middle-class) boys are (Hickling-Hudson, 1992, pp. 1-21). In the world of work, the
kind of contact women have with computers tends to reinforce women's
marginalization. Computer technology reflects and reinforces existing relations
of power in society. Postman has special
concerns about the impact that technology in the classroom can have on social
relationships. In introducing the
personal computer to the classroom, we shall be breaking a four-hundred-year-old
truce between the gregariousness and openness fostered by orality
and the introspection and isolation fostered by the printed word. Orality stresses group learning, cooperation, and a sense
of social responsibility ... Now comes the computer, carrying anew the banner
of private learning and individual problem-solving. Will the widespread use of
computers in the classroom defeat once and for all the claims of communal
speech? (Postman, 1993, p. 17) Educational
Computing: Elementary Insights The promise and
paranoia of technology in society are duplicated in our schools, with zealots
guaranteeing educational transformation, and critics warning of the development
of a generation of antisocial nerds. If technology has earned mixed reviews in
society, what is its school report card? The Apple
Classrooms of Tomorrow (ACOT) project in the At the post
secondary level, too, researchers are cautious about crediting technology with
educational improvement. Schierman and Jones
acknowledge that there is an assumption that technology is de facto beneficial
to educational endeavors. However, they conclude from comprehensive, large-scale
analyses of reports of benefit (e.g. Wilkenson 1980;
Clark 1983) "that claims of large gains in achievement are not warranted
and, indeed, that the attribution of measurable gains in achievement to the use
of any educational technology should be viewed with caution, since factors
other than those cited as the cause of achievement gains may be
responsible" (Schierman and Jones, 1996, p. 65). Nonetheless, the
technology has its champions who say that achievements online are equal or
superior to those generated in face-to-face situations (Harasim
et al, 1996, p. 27). Harasim and her colleagues argue
that the primary goals of the virtual classroom are to improve both the access
to educational opportunities, and the quality of the educational process
itself. They claim that in the majority of cases, these goals were achieved (Harasim et al, 1996, p. 88). Furthermore, they
argue that, "Active learning is a major outcome of learning networks"
(Harasim et al, 1996, p. 29). Indeed, they seem to
claim that because of technology, learning environments are more democratic,
teachers and students are more respectful of group knowledge, interaction is increased, and is of better quality (Harasim et al, 1996, p. 28). Chris Dede is another who extols the virtues of virtual education
claiming that, The innovative
pedagogies empowered by these emerging media, messages, and experiences make
possible an evolution ...into an alternative instructional paradigm:
distributed learning. In particular, advances in computer- supported
collaborative learning, multi-media/hypermedia, and experiential simulation
offer the potential to create shared 'learning-through-doing environments'
available any place and any time. (Dede, 1996, p. 4) Why Bother? The implications of
the technology are complex, the jury is not yet in on
the benefits. As busy educators, from Kindergarten to post-secondary levels,
the choices about technology in our classrooms are troublesome. We could ignore
it, committing ourselves to the classical tradition. We could leap on the
bandwagon and hope we can determine where it is going. We could be fatalistic,
acknowledging the inevitability of the technological takeover of our social and
intellectual lives and admitting to our own powerlessness in the face of it. We
could engage critically, applying our own skills of scholarship and accepting
the responsibility for advocacy that accompanies our chosen profession. Assuming that
technology will not be absent from the future of the students we teach, we
support Penley and Ross's call for the creation of a technoliterate critical mass. While acknowledging that
"the odds are firmly stacked against the efforts of those committed to
creating technological countercultures," they argue that there is a
"pressing need for more, rather than less, technoliteracy
- a crucial requirement not just for purposes of postmodern survival but also
for the task of decolonizing, demonopolizing, and
democratizing social communication" (Penley and
Ross, 1991). Technoliteracy is the work of the classroom. Technology as
Trojan Horse Post-secondary
institutions are experiencing their own "new economy" of competition,
shortages of resources, and drive for "market share" in the form of
recruitment of students and "increased productivity" of faculty. Technology
is promised as a solution to these campus problems, one that will reduce costs,
improve teaching, provide evidence of the "currency" of the
institution, and help graduates develop the job specific skills that will make
them employable in Rifkin's brave new world. Technology, of
course, will not necessarily do any of these things. It does seem however, to
attract endowments and contributions from corporations, and it seems to be an
aspect of campus infrastructure that even cash-strapped institutions will
consider as an investment. It may also introduce enough tension and dissonance
in the traditional classroom as to provide opportunity for teachers and
students to examine the way they work together. There is some evidence that
when one change occurs, all things suddenly seem to be open to review. In arguing that
technological change is ecological, says that It is not possible
to contain the effects of a new technology to a limited sphere of human
activity...one significant change generates total change (Postman, 1993, p.
18). Critical Engagement
With the Technology The ACOT reviewers
reported that their project provided an opportunity to demonstrate how children
and schools could work differently. They described technology as an engaging
medium for student thought and collaboration, and claimed that the smart (our
emphasis) use of technology could increase student academic performance and
support the acquisition of a whole new set of twenty-first-century competencies
(Fisher et al, 1994, p. 29). What is a smart use
of technology, and who are the smart users? Is Harasim
correct that active learning is an outcome of online education, or is online
learning only productive if it is active? Are teachers who use technology
smartly predisposed to democratic, collaborative, problem based pedagogy, or
does technology bring these behaviors into the classroom? Can we analyze the
impact of technology separate from the impact of teaching with technology? Does
improved student learning occur only when technology is introduced along with
different teaching practices? What teaching practices are best suited to
maximizing the potential of technology to improve student learning? Or more
fundamentally, what teaching practices are best suited to improving student learning? The attributes that
Harasim assigns to online learning can and do exist
in thriving non-wired classrooms, especially at the elementary level. A similar
set of attributes appears as the Principles of Learning established by the
Government of the Learning requires
the active participation of the student People learn in a
variety of ways and at different rates Learning is both an
individual and a group process. (British Columbia Ministry of Education, 1993) It is the expectation
of the government, at least theoretically, that in all classrooms learning will
be "purposive, reflective, negotiated, critical, complex, situation
driven, and engaged" (British Columbia Ministry of Education, 1993),
emerging technology or no emerging technology. A closer look at Dede's 'technologically empowered' pedagogies reveals that
they are analogical, case-based, learning-by-doing ... giving learners
constructivist experiences, facilitating comprehension and ability to
generalize ... structuring group dialogue and decision making, facilitating
collective activities. (Dede, 1996, p. 13) While it may be
pointless to have a "what came first" debate about technology and
critical pedagogy, we must concede their interrelatedness. It is important to
focus our attention on what Fenstermacher calls the
"manner and method" (Fenstermacher, 1992),
or Postman the "metaphysical and mechanical" Postman, 1995) of
teaching. To fail to recognize, as Cuban says, "Our character as human
beings and how we teach become what we teach" (Cuban, 1992, p. 9) is to
concentrate on the carving tools while ignoring the sculptor. Martin Haberman puts it bluntly, "No school can be better
than its teachers" (Haberman, 1995, p. 777). He
calls for teachers to know what they do and why they do it. The technology they
use is not neutral, nor is their pedagogy. The ACOT researchers found that
well-grounded teachers were positioned to make the most of new tools. Classroom
innovators are often teachers who have strong beliefs about how students can learn, a passion for teaching, and some idea of how
technology can help everyone involved to do things a little better or a little
differently. (Fisher et al, 1994, p. 207) And, ACOT
indicated, teachers made fundamental changes in their practice. Over time, ACOT's design changed from computer saturation which
supported the existing knowledge transfer approach to learning, to the current
emphasis on routine access where technologies are used to support
collaborative, project-based knowledge construction. (Fisher et al, 1994, p.
268) Experienced
designers of distance education programs at the post-secondary level concur
that good learning experiences for students are the result of careful
foresight. We invite course
designers to foster the open-ended, collaborative, and reflective processes
that this medium can deliver, while still relying on conventional ISD models as
heuristics. Designers need to attend to both the role and the extent of online
activities to their total course, as well as seek a match among teacher,
learner, format and content. (Berg and Collins, 1996, p. 79) Further, there are
specific teaching behaviors that seem to be influential at the Virtual U. Harasim says a learner-centered (rather than teacher-centered) model
has been found as the best fit online. CMC is meant for the sharing and
building of ideas, information and skills among the participants to strengthen
knowledge building, integration and application of conceptual information. (Harasim et al, 1996, p. 24) She devotes
considerable attention to the consequences of moving from teacher to
facilitator, identifying key behaviors that may or may not exist
"offline" but are considered essential to successful teaching online,
including setting the stage, monitoring and encouraging participation, forming
groups, assigning role responsibilities, moderating and facilitating group
processes, establishing norms and grading performance. While Paulsen
acknowledges that "moderators [of computer conferences] will perceive their
role ... in light of their basic theories and philosophies toward
education," he cites the work of Mason, Forsyth and Brochet
in identifying "task roles and socioemotional
roles", "organizational, social and intellectual roles" or the
contribution of the moderator as "goal setter, discriminator, host, pace
setter, explainer, entertainer" to ensure a successful computer conference
(Paulsen, 1996, p. 83). Rohfeld and Hiemstra, too, define
the electronic classroom as a place for collaborative learning. They return to
the "essence" of learning, plugged in or not. Teaching through
discussion relies on a learner- centered approach, whether the participants
meet face to face or on the computer screen. It rests on principles of
collaborative learning and egalitarian relationships." (Rohfeld and Hiemstra, 1996, p.
91) Because helping
learners take increasing control over personal learning is a goal for most
educational endeavors, computer-mediated conferencing can be supportive of such
fundamental educational values. (Rohfeld and Hiemstra, 1996, p. 102) The preponderance
of references to student-centered learning, a democratic learning environment,
the shared construction of knowledge and the changing of teaching practices in
these reviews of the positive presence of technology on campus persuades us that technology and critical pedagogy have a
promising relationship. Still, the improvement of pedagogy is a good end in
itself, and critical pedagogy has a role larger than guiding learning online. Critical Engagement
About the Technology It is not enough
for educators to provide students with a map of the information highway. There
are critical questions to consider about highways in general, and how humans
travel through their environment. Introducing new
technologies into our classrooms is an activity of great consequence, because,
like other technological change, it is the re-tooling of the social. Postman
reminds us that New technologies
alter the structure of our interests: the things we think about. They alter the
character of our symbols: the things we think with. And they alter the nature
of community: the arena in which thoughts develop. (Postman, 1993, p. 20) At the same time,
in urging us to avoid demonizing technology, Haraway
argues that the boundary between the "natural" and the
"artificial," i.e. the technological, is entirely political. She
points out that we fear the technology that is alien, while we welcome other
technology, such as the contact lens, the ball point pen, general anesthesia,
convincing ourselves that it is not "really" technology (Haraway, 1991). This confusion characterizes our failure to
view technology as social practice and hence in need of the same attention and
skepticism that would accompany say, a change in policy with respect to legal
drinking age. By recognizing technologies as social in origin and social in
consequence, we provide ourselves with a much needed critical foothold to
engage with the technology, and to engage about the technology. Research and debate
in classrooms at all levels about the politics of technology should surround
any skill building technology curriculum. The Politics of
Post-Secondary Teaching What support is
there for post secondary educators to develop and nurture the beliefs and
skills of critical pedagogy that seem to undergird success with emerging
technologies? Kearsley argues " ... we are still
trying to employ 19th century pedagogical ideas in the 21st century.' ... A
vast conceptual gap exists between the kinds of technologically based learning
and teaching methods that Chris Dede is talking about
and those practiced in almost every classroom and training center. Never mind
whether suitable hardware and software is available to teachers and students to
carry out such endeavors (it is not). Wholly missing on the part of most
teachers is the knowledge of such methods, the opportunity to try out and
practice such methods, and the time to think through ways to change the
curriculum to incorporate these methods" (Kearsley,
1996, p. 57). The Carnegie
Foundation for the Advancement of Teaching conducted a series of surveys with
5,000 faculty members in 1989 to clarify the status of the professoriate and to
provide a portrait of American higher education, including the balance between
teaching and research. The majority of these faculty reported that they
consider teaching to be a central mission of the university and a rewarding
activity but that the reward system of their institutions was heavily weighted
towards published research rather than effective teaching (Boyer, 1990). In a
subsequent study of the relative importance of teaching, research,
administration, and service in determining basic salary, involving more than
4,000 full-time, tenure-track faculty in four-year colleges and universities, James
Fairweather reports that teaching activities seldom
were rewarded. In some cases, time spent on teaching was negatively related to
salary. Results showed the dominance of a research-oriented faculty reward
structure for each type of institution regardless of professed mission. Reward
structures favouring good teaching are lacking even
in the four-year liberal arts colleges whose specific mission focuses on
undergraduate teaching. Boyer concludes that without significant changes in
institutional reward structure, teaching at the post-secondary level will not
improve appreciably. Faculty preparation
in graduate school continues to offer very little or no instruction on how to
teach. Faculty continue to rely on the teaching
methods they have always used - this despite research documenting the need for
students to learn actively. More often than not the choice of instructional
method is a habitual one rather than a reasoned decision based on the
instructional objectives of the course and content for the day.... college
teachers teach pretty much as they were taught. (Weimer, 1990, p. xi) Some institutions
have established a specific unit on campus to provide instructional support
resources. New hirings include more attention to
teaching record than in the past. Still the reward systems
remain fundamentally unchanged and does not contribute to an environment
hospitable for the Trojan horse of technology. Not only must teaching itself be
deemed important, but teaching itself must get serious attention. Once again,
the K-12 teachers offer good counsel that the introduction of new technologies
must be accompanied by a commitment to teacher development. The ACOT projects
acknowledged that "Successful technology use implies both change of
underlying frameworks as well as the incorporation and appropriation of
technology benefits into classroom practices" (Fisher et al, 1996, p.
199). They point out that for innovative programs to be successful, training and
staff- development components should constitute approximately 30 to 40 percent
of the total effort. This effort should include: structured observation of accomplished practice reflection on and discussion of teaching and learning hands-on, collaborative learning curriculum project development teacher teams and [administrator] participation commitment to share with colleagues follow-up support support for accomplished teachers iterative expansion plans (Fisher et al, 1996, p. 243). Francis Oakley
notes that the appropriate use of technology requires organizational change. We
suggest that the very organizational change required for the appropriate use of
technology in educational contexts is the provision of supports for good
teaching. Without time and resources for professional development and without a
reward structure that responds to pedagogical development by faculty members,
educational technology will be hard pressed to deliver on any of its promises. Really, Why Bother? Critical pedagogy
facilitates the development of a language of critical discourse. If we use it
as a social force we may be able to foster a generation of technoliterate
skeptics, equipping our society to engage critically with both the content and
the consequences of new technologies. Support for this critical engagement is
an important contribution educators can make to efforts to trouble boundaries
between insiders and outsiders as society shifts and changes. Elementary teachers
know that hungry children don't learn much beyond the immediate experience of
having their basic needs unmet. And yet school lunch programs are hotly
contested in school district and state politics. Educational settings mirror,
or at least are structured in relation to, the larger social context. The
politics of hunger and exclusion in the elementary context have their parallels
in post-secondary institutions where institutional practices have remained
virtually untouched through the post-war era. However, recent
climate studies and challenges to the canon have revealed institutional
practices of discrimination. They, in turn have met with a backlash against
so-called political correctness. When considering educational technologies,
post- secondary educators need to confront the ways in which technologies are
likely to line up in the construction of boundaries between insiders and
outsiders on campus, and whether this system break will permit the re-tooling
of the social in a liberating way. It might be that
educational technologies bring with them to campus the resources, time, and
attention that enable educators to engage critically about the social. It may
be that failure to engage critically will enable the emerging technologies to
entrench outsider educational and social practices. We see the technoliterate skeptic participating in critical dialogue
with her peers as the only person able to function as a citizen in the face of
these dilemmas. The role of the educator in modelling
this skepticism cannot be overemphasized. Yes, we really should bother. Menzies refers to the information highway as a restructuring
agent (Menzies, 1996). The argument we've made in favour of engaging with educational technology can be
summarized rather bluntly: restructure or be restructured! Pedagogics is a normative science with its own subject of
research. The historical development of pedagogical thought shows strong
relations with philosophical-anthropological principles and with
historical-cultural characteristics. Education today is confronted with, among
other things, postmodern developments in society ('Hauslosigkeit')
and a change in patterns of youth behavior (from a standard career to a chosen
career). For pedagogical analysis, a renewed appeal to reason is advocated. A
suitable method is the triadic-pedagogical analysis, which reflects on the
parent-child relation in connection with historical-cultural developments. We can safely assume that everyone
is aware that children cannot be left to fend for themselves and that they
cannot become adult on their own. However, not everyone is convinced that the
process of growing up and gradually growing into society requires an on-going
pedagogic relationship based on more or less pronounced concepts of what it is
to be a civilized human being. "It can't be allowed!" people cry when
they hear that school children are carrying weapons and that they use them on a
regular basis. A father will say that his children need a "good
education" so that they can come to occupy a "good position" in
society. While a mother might say that as far as she is concerned, the most
important thing is that her children should be "honest" and that they
should learn to be prepared to help one another. In all of these cases there is
clearly some notion of the relationship between education and the socio-cultural
environment, of the current state of society and society as it might be, of
what should be considered normal or abnormal in terms of human behavior and of
the kinds of things that education can strive towards. But not everyone is
willing to accept the practical pedagogic consequences that these notions imply
-- in other words, the need to maintain an on-going pedagogic relationship in
which educators care for the children in their charge, are aware of their
responsibility and are also ethically responsible, relating to the surrounding
culture critically and consciously and making every effort to enable children
to take part in society responsibly and effectively in their own way. Consciously or otherwise, educators
allow themselves to be guided by all kinds of values regarding human existence
on a daily basis and these values are concretized in their dealings with the
children they are educating through the setting of various standards. If
educators do not allow themselves to be guided by values, there will be no
rules or any rules that do exist will be arbitrarily applied. Or there will be
a naive faith that with a bit of good will’s everything will work out all right
on its own. This kind of attitude means that the child is indeed left to fend
for itself and fails to learn to make choices and to be responsible for them. A
child may well be able to grow up in such a situation, but is not given enough
assistance in the process of becoming an adult. For, like Langeveld,
we are also of the opinion that while growing up the child simultaneously
engages in a process in which it determines and shapes the values that it has
learned or discovered while growing up increasingly independently (Langeveld, 1979, p.23). In this respect, to continue to
think along the lines of Langeveld's pedagogics, we are concerned with development, education
and self-forming within a context of relatively constant personal
relationships. However, the pedagogic relationship never exists entirely
independently of the historical-cultural context. Thus in this respect we also
share Imelman's view that the educator and the child
being educated are also affected by the formative influence of the cultural
environment. Ultimately, the task of pedagogics is to
act as a mediator within this process. Concerned as it is with the
legitimization of pedagogic procedures, theoretical pedagogics
has always had to account for the reasons for education and even the necessity
for education. Pedagogics per se, that is, for while
those who are purely concerned with the therapeutic side of pedagogics
-- questioning the effectiveness of certain approaches and strategies, such as
how to deal with bed-wetting, eating disorders or social anxiety -- are
covering important ground for the practice of pedagogics,
they are not obliged to account for their actions from the point of view of
cultural pedagogics, nor are they considered to have
any responsibility towards the child in question in the longer term. However,
the discipline of pedagogics per se -- in other
words, the aspect of pedagogics that cannot be
reduced to psychology (or any other behavioral science) -- cannot evade the
issue of legitimization. Beekman states it in the following lofty terms "A
science of education that does not make any value judgments is a valueless
science of education." In 1826 Friedrich Schleiermacher, one of the
founders of academic pedagogics, went as far as to
characterize pedagogics as applied ethics. It is
worth bearing in mind that Schleiermacher conceived of ethics as cultural philosophy
as an evolutionary process ('progress'), but all the same! In the tradition of pedagogics as an aspect of the humanities it is common
practice to base pedagogical reasoning on statements regarding the human being
taken from philosophical anthropology. Some of these statements have since
become such established ideas in pedagogic theory that their origin is no
longer known. Here, by way of example, we look at the anthropological ideas
expounded by Scheler, Portmann
and, above all, by Gehlen, who is so widely quoted in
the formulation of pedagogic theory. With reference to Nietzsche, Gehlen describes man as "the not-yet-determined
animal". Who and what man is or must become still remains to be seen. According to Gehlen
(1940) this fact, which is an unusual phenomenon within nature, makes man
"a creature of discipline". This notion implies a clear task for
education, suggesting that without the imposition of discipline the human being
will not become a true human being or in any event will not be given his due.
Similar ideas had already been voiced earlier, by Kant, for example, in his Vorlesung ьber Pдdagogik (1776): "We understand by education
namely care, discipline and instruction besides cultivation".' (Kant,
1803, p. 697: "Unter Erziehung
nдmlich verstehen wir die Wartung, Disziplin, Unterweisung nebst der Bildung")
The quotation from Gehlen referred to above is one of a series of statements
regarding the human individual that attempt to clarify man's special status
within nature and in the world. The human being is considered to differ from
the animal in that he comes into the world incomplete and has to act in an open
world in order to be able to survive, for, unlike the animal, the human being
is unable to rely on the safety of innate instincts. A newborn infant is unable
to act on its own. It needs assistance and therefore needs to be educated. Yet
even when man is fully grown the task is still not complete, for as an adult
the individual is called upon to make something of him and must continue to act
in order to be able to maintain this position. However, like children, adults do
not need to do this on their own. For -- to pursue Gehlen's
argument -- human beings are also characterized by the fact that together they
create a culture which functions as a second nature within which they can live
a human life especially with the aid of institutions (defined as a collection
of models of action and/or patterns of behaviour,
examples of which include the state, the legal system, the family, school, work
and religion). According to this way of thinking the human individual comes
into the world unspecialized and finds within himself, as it were, the mandate
to act. Initially the child is unable to act independently and until it can act
independently it needs help. Pedagogues adopt this anthropological finding as
the rationale for educational action. Thus we come to one of the fundamental
principles of pedagogic action, which may or may not be explicitly stated. Gehlen's anthropology does not stand alone. It exists within
the context of a series of anthropologies, being preceded by the work of Scheler and Plessner, among
others, which also had an effect on pedagogics, and
followed by the work of Sartre, Levinas and Derrida,
among others. Research into the fundamental principles of pedagogics
might seek to examine such a series of anthropologies not only in terms of the
way in which they have been received by pedagogics
but also in terms of their (practical) utility. To a certain extent the history of pedagogics is a history of concepts of man in relation to
education. But, one might object, isn't all education highly individual and
situational in practice, embedded in the historical-cultural environment, which
is not derived from all kinds of general anthropological systems? And to pursue
this line of thinking still further: Isn't the theory of education excessively
divorced from the practice of education which is essentially self-governing and
relatively autonomous? The tradition of the humanities goes as far as to speak
of theoretical clarification in retrospect, thereby acknowledging the primacy
of practice. To some extent the praxis itself determines its own course
(Schleiermacher speaks of the "dignity of praxis"). Given that this is the case, the
theory of education is increasingly being assigned the task of critically
reflecting on what has already occurred and acting as an 'interlocutor' for
future practitioners. One thing is certain, when it comes to the discipline of pedagogics the question of theory and practice can never be
reduced to the simple application of scientific conclusions in practice. Among
other things, scientific opinions are too divided for this to be possible,
there being very little consensus from one paradigm to another. As a result,
the scientific nature of pedagogics is constantly
subject to discussion. The relationship between philosophy and science has yet
to crystallize. To return to the question of the unique and
unrepeatable nature of each educational situation this is another aspect
covered by philosophical anthropology that is regularly considered in pedagogics. The various personalistic
notions in pedagogics are interesting in this
respect. In the twentieth century in particular examples of this kind of
thinking can be seen in various countries, in the work of Pascal, Kierkegaard
and in the Judeo-Christian tradition (Buber, Maritain), among others. Personalistic thinking centers on the human individual as a person.
As a person-in-the-making the child is charged with the task of realizing its
intention in a dialectical relationship with the other. Again this is
considered to justify the existence of education, for children need help in
order to be able to do this. The process of self-realization, which is less
concerned with capitalizing on one's potential than with finding one's specific
purpose in life (which may or may not be interpreted in a religious sense),
does not really lend itself to empirical research within the context of
developmental psychology, nevertheless it has consistently inspired the
thinking regarding education. In this case the human being is considered to be
the architect of his own destiny and, as a pupil or student, is partly
responsible for his own education. This view has been convincingly
elaborated by the Italian pedagogue Guiseppe Flores d'Arcais who is not as well-known as he should be in the Above all, In addition to elaborating on the
education of the individual and the kind of assistance that promotes personal
development, triadic pedagogics also elaborates on
the process involved in the transmission and renewal of human culture. Thanks
above all to Imelman, the transmission and renewal of
human culture has been extracted from the relatively obscure and ambiguous
atmosphere in the relationship between the educator and the child and subjected
to a clear analysis in the triadic model. Something (a certain point of view)
is always communicated. The point of view (or aspect of knowledge) in question
is partly reflected in the pedagogic analysis. In this case, rather than focusing
on a theory regarding the pedagogic relationship, we are concerned with an
analysis of the triangular relationship between the child, the educator and the
point of view being communicated. It hardly needs to be emphasized that such an
analysis is also likely to include anthropological factors. A rational and
objectifying approach to the transfer of knowledge within the context of the
teaching-learning process encourages the pupils to process knowledge critically
and helps to prevent the unquestioning absorption of knowledge. The
anthropological principle that applies in this case is that the human child
should be educated as a rational (and responsible) being. The considerations outlined above
are some of the standard issues addressed by program-oriented theories of
education, particularly within the tradition of the humanities. Pedagogues who
lean towards conceptual analysis can therefore claim that they have already
dealt with this aspect, given that conceptual analysis is concerned with
distinguishing between meaning and nonsense, fiction and reality. In the same
way, descriptive scientists can question the empirical and practical relevance
of the entire anthropological body of thought. In this respect we are all too
well aware of the theoretical diversity that exists within the field of
pedagogic science. So to sum up the ideas set out
above: Pedagogic reasoning is often based
on ideas developed by philosophical anthropology. Dominant anthropological
principles in pedagogics are man as the
not-yet-determined animal and man as a creature of discipline; the human being
as an unspecialized being living in an open world; the human being as a
rational being. Educational theory is often based on anthropological
reflections, seen from the point of view of natural development, cultural
philosophy or personalism. An analysis of the central
question addressed by pedagogics (what needs to be
taught to whom, when, how and why?) is likely to be enhanced by an
anthropologically based study of educational reality. In the introduction, taking our lead
from Langeveld, we wrote that the purpose of
education is to promote development and self-forming within the context of
relatively constant personal relationships. In most cases the education that
occurs within the context classic family education is conveyed within the home.
In traditional pedagogics the kind of education that
takes place within the household is adopted as the model for residential forms
of education. Pestalozzi uses the terms "Wohnstubenerziehung"
(living-room education) and the "Wohnstubengeist"
(living-room atmosphere) that should ideally prevail in professional education.
Domesticity involves a certain naturalness (Schleiermacher describes education
within the home by the child's biological parents as the "natural starting
point of education") and also includes emotional-affective factors and a
coherent community in terms of concepts and attitudes. Today -- two centuries on -- the
home is still the main scene of action, though there have been a number of
essential changes in the intervening period. For one thing, children of a very
young age now spend one or more days a week at crčches
and day care centers, children are made to start school younger and younger,
the large number of divorces and second and third marriages mean that many
children grow up in a number of (step) families, older children leave the
family earlier to live in lodgings, or, alternatively, they continue to live at
home for longer, or leave the family home only to return again and again (the
so-called boomerang kids). In other words, the family home is increasingly
characterized by huge diversity. In addition to this, from the point
of view of transmission the 'home' represents something far more fundamental.
In this respect Buber speaks of Hauslosigkeit
(homelessness in a figurative sense) as a characteristic feature of modern
culture. According to Buber, the home -- in the sense of a shared ideology --
has gradually been demolished. This has implications for interpersonal
relationships and life within society at large. Shared values and standards can
no longer be taken for granted. Tying in with this, many of the
French postmodernist thinkers (Lyotard and Derrida
among others) claim that the "main storylines" (the grands rйcits) have lost
their credibility. In saying so they are referring not only to the decline of
the Christian world view, which was widely upheld in the past, but -- more
broadly -- to all secularized forms of Judeo-Christian theology subscribed to in
the past, to the myth of human progress being achieved by means of science and
technology, and, more generally, to all of the stories that people have used to
help make the world and their own lives more understandable. In the postmodern
culture the human individual is forced to live without a home, as it were. And
"a homeless person is a disoriented person!" (Sperna Weiland, 1999, pp. 347 and
364). The postmodernists deny that there
are any central truths; they emphasize the pluriformity
of reality (differential philosophy) and thus confirm what Nietzsche said a
century earlier: "There is no such thing as absolute truth." On the
other hand, there are countless perspectives from which to examine reality. The
same applies to the understanding of text: there is no single meaning or no
single truth. Similarly, deconstruction teaches that there is no text, there is
only interpretation. Postmodern principles are not
confined to the philosophy of architecture, they also characterize social
reality. This is not something that pedagogics can
afford to overlook since these principles permeate the "Volk- und
Zeitgeist" (Jean Paul). Faced with these postmodern principles we need to
ask what are the pedagogic implications of these postmodern developments? Or,
in the light of the ideas set out above, how does 'Hauslosigkeit'
affect "relatively constant personal relationships" and the child's
natural tendency to "determine and shape the values that it has learned or
discovered increasingly independent" (Langeveld)
and the endeavour to teach young people to think
critically and to communicate an awareness of values (Imelman)? What is 'modern youth'? Before we can
answer the key question addressed by this article, we first need to have some
idea of the distinguishing characteristics of modern youth. Sociologists
concerned with juveniles frequently conduct research studies on this subject.
The juvenile sociological research department in According to Du Bois-Reymond the juvenile phase is under pressure. This phase
now involves the characteristic aspects of individualization and pluriformity, freedom of choice and forced choices, a
negotiation culture combined with informalization,
and the movement from a standard career to an ą la carte career. Young people now stay at school
longer. The longer period of education and increased peer pressure is changing
the relationship between young people and their parents. Parents increasingly
have to compete with the standards and way of life of their children's peers.
The traditional nuclear family of father, mother and child now exists alongside
other ways of living: communities of unmarried adults with children, divorced
parents, single parents or guardians. There has been a wholesale extension of
the youth phase with a distinction being made between post-adolescents and
young adults. Young people now have more freedom of choice but have to be able
to legitimize their choices. Compared with a few decades ago
juveniles no longer follow a set life pattern on their way towards adulthood.
The sequence of status passages (the transition from one life situation to the
next, such as the transition from school to higher education or the transition
from living at home to living alone) is now unpredictable. There is no longer
such a thing as a standard career -- it is now more appropriate to think in
terms of ą la carte career. The aspect of choice is also evident at
secondary school. Du Bois-Reymond observes that
"The compulsory national cultural curriculum [...] is giving way in favour of more choice". "The relationship between
parents and juveniles is now far more intimate, freer and more congenial than
was previously the case." "The present intimacy in families -- call
it domestic negotiation -- has an aspect of uncertainty [...] in the sense that
future is now an uncertain factor for all members of society, regardless of
their age." "This has to do with the labor market which is now
unpredictable." In addition to the research on the
juvenile phase being carried out in Though we may agree that it is
helpful and possibly even necessary to educate a child, we are still not sure
precisely what kind of education we are talking about. A broad awareness of the
need for education does not automatically imply that there is unanimity
regarding the content of the educational activity. Above we saw that to some
extent the definition of education is based on anthropological assumptions.
Conditions, methods and objectives all vary depending on the prevailing view of
the human individual, among other things. Arguing that naturalness was primary,
Rousseau defended the idea that the child must be educated to become the human
being that nature intended him to be since the child was unable to achieve this
on its own and cultural influences simply had an adverse effect. Writing at approximately the same
time, Lessing claimed that a child could be educated given that education
simply served to accelerate and facilitate the process of becoming a human
being that was already underway. As far as Lessing was concerned, the belief in
progress that was one of the main tenets of the Enlightenment included the idea
of education. For this reason it was important to subject society to
constructive criticism (and not to turn away from society as Rousseau
advocated), for this would also accelerate the process of society becoming more
rational. Agreeing with the principles voiced
by Rousseau and Lessing, Pestalozzi -- who was also writing in around 1800 --
was in favour of a method of education that drew on
the natural development of the child and he also devoted a great deal of effort
to the creation a better society. Accepting the biologically established incompleteness
and unspecializedness of the human child who, in
addition to this, also lives in an open world, one-and-a-half centuries later Gehlen felt it necessary to emphasize the need for
discipline (see the first paragraph of this article). However, pedagogics
is usually more complex than this tends to suggest. For besides seeing the
corruption of nature (which he wished to restore) Pestalozzi also saw an unjust
society (which he wished to change) and in addition to this he was also an
ardently religious man. As might be expected, all of these different aspects
are reflected in his concept of education. The later interpretations of his
work sometimes focus exclusively on one aspect, giving the impression that
there were several Pestalozzis (or should we
acknowledge that these interpretations are all true in the way that
postmodernism recognizes the validity of different interpretations). The confusion got worse still when
in 1996 writers in And it gets more complex still if we
attempt to visualize education under conditions of postmodernity.
Postmodernist theory may well help to clarify the issues faced by modern-day
education, by establishing a connection between Hauslosigkeit,
the sense of disorientation and the teaching of values. Yet it is difficult to
conceive of a practice of education deliberately based on the body of
postmodernist thought. For what does the educator have to offer the child if
the educator constantly points to the wealth of perspectives, denying the
existence of absolute truth and relativizing all
explanatory associations? The application of postmodernist
theory in educational situations presupposes that any such theory would first
be comprehensively formulated as a pedagogic approach before there could be any
practical consequences. Generally speaking, leaving aside the question as to
whether such an approach would actually be desirable, children are
uncomfortable with uncertainty or with a wealth of perspectives and the relativization of values. For the rest, it is possible to
conceive of an educational theory that draws on insights expounded by
differential philosophy, for example. Even if it is only that on the basis of
this philosophy the gender aspect of education can be elaborated in a new way. If the attempt to define precisely
what we mean by the term 'education' and to identify the kinds of assumptions
are at issue proves problematic within the context of a single concept of education,
it is hardly surprising that it will be even more difficult to arrive at unequivocality and unanimity within the science of
education as a whole. History shows a kaleidoscopic picture of standard
concepts of education and in our day the science of education is still
characterized by a diversity of concepts and methods. The answer to the
question "What is education?" gives rise to a picture of diverse
activities. However, when it comes to a general description of the terrain,
Kant's definition (1803) still stands. Education encompasses the following four
aspects: nurture and protection, the teaching of rules (discipline),
instruction and training. Education is a matter of
"cheerful seriousness", but serious all the same. In order to prevent
a situation in which pedagogics lapses into
unfortunate relativism ("there is no such thing as absolute truth")
or degenerates into a supermarket model ("every customer selects something
to suit his taste"), it is necessary to establish certain a priori rights
of the child being educated (possibly based on the UN declaration regarding the
rights of the child, or on other respectable and broadly upheld principles,
such as Albert Schweitzer's maxim of "Respect for life"). As far as
the science of education is concerned, it is important to state explicitly, as
far as possible, the basic principles being subscribed to. If it is true that young people have
never been faced with as much uncertainty as they are in our time (in the sense
of 'Hauslosigkeit', looser family ties, unrelenting
dictatorship of choice, uncertain expectations with regard to the future, a
potpourri attitude towards values and standards, etc.), it is all the more
necessary to subject education and training to the critical authority of
reason. As formulated by Imelman and Meijer in
triadic pedagogics: education in which pupils are
taught to ask teachers to account for the subject matter being taught, and
teachers are asked to account for what they are teaching by means of the game
of reducing uncertainty. The idea is that pupils should be able to gain a
thorough command of the subject they are being taught, in other words, that
they should reflect on what they are learning and assume responsibility and in
doing so create a hold on life. This is a prerequisite for the child to be able
to develop into a person. And in a scientific sense a permanently critical
outlook that does not shy from criticizing sacred cows in the interest of
education. Or, as formulated by Bollnow in his anthropological pedagogics,
an education in which a permanent appeal is made to the (development of the)
inner reason of the child. Education is more necessary than ever, an education
that continues to be a true subject of conversation: "Since we are a
conversation and can listen to each other" (Hцlderlin). Pedagogy is also occasionally referred to as the correct use of
instructive strategies (see instructional theory). For example, Paulo Freire referred to his method of teaching adult humans as
"critical pedagogy". In correlation with those instructive strategies
the instructor's own philosophical beliefs of instruction are harbored and
governed by the pupil's background knowledge and experience, situation, and
environment, as well as learning goals set by the student and teacher. One
example would be the Socratic schools of thought The Latin-derived word for pedagogy: child-instruction,
is in modern use in English to refer to the whole context of instruction,
learning, and the actual operation involved therein, although both words have
roughly the same original meaning.
In English the term pedagogy is used to refer to instructive theory; trainee
teachers learn their subject and also the pedagogy appropriate for teaching
that subject. The introduction of information technology into schools has
necessitated changes in pedagogy; teachers are adopting new methods of teaching
facilitated by the new technology. The late Malcolm Knowles reasoned that the
term andragogy is more pertinent when discussing
adult learning and teaching. He referred to andragogy
as the art and science of teaching adults. THE present is the age of
intellectualism. The intellect is that faculty of soul in the exercise of which
man's inner being participates least. One speaks with some justification of the
cold intellectual nature; we need only reflect how the intellect acts upon
artistic perception or practice. It dispels or impedes. And artists dread that
their creations may be conceptually or symbolically explained by the
intelligence. In the clarity of the intellect the warmth of soul which, in the
act of creation, gave life to their works, is extinguished. The artist would
like his work to be grasped by feeling, not by the understanding. For then the
warmth with which he has experienced it is communicated to the beholder. But
this warmth is repelled by an intellectual explanation. In social life intellectualism
separates men from one another. They can only work rightly within the community
when they are able to impart to their deeds — which always involve the weal or
woe of their fellow beings — something of their soul. One man should experience
not only another's activity but something of his soul. In a deed, however,
which springs from intellectualism, a man withholds his soul nature. He does
not let it flow over to his neighbour. It has long
been said that in the teaching and training of children intellectualism
operates in a crippling way. In saying this one has in mind, in the first
place, only the child's intelligence, not the teacher's. One would like to
fashion one's methods of training and instruction so that not only the child's
cold understanding may be aroused and developed, but warmth of heart may be
engendered too. The anthroposophical
view of the world is in full agreement with this. It accepts fully the
excellent educational maxims which have grown from this demand. But it realises clearly that warmth can only be imparted from soul
to soul. On this account it holds that, above all, pedagogy itself must become ensouled, and thereby the teachers' whole activity. In recent times intellectualism has
permeated strongly into methods of instruction and training. It has achieved
this indirectly, by way of modern science. Parents let science dictate what is
good for the child's body, soul and spirit. And teachers, during their
training, receive from science the spirit of their educational methods. But science has achieved its
triumphs precisely through intellectualism. It wants to keep its thoughts free
of anything from man's own soul life, letting them receive everything from
sense observation and experiment. Such a science could build up the excellent
knowledge of nature of our time, but it cannot found a true pedagogy. A true pedagogy must be based upon a
knowledge that embraces man with respect to body, soul and spirit.
Intellectualism only grasps man with respect to his body, for to observation
and experiment the bodily alone is revealed. Before a true pedagogy can be
founded, a true knowledge of man is necessary. This Anthroposophy seeks to attain. One cannot come to a knowledge of man by first forming an idea of his bodily
nature with the help of a science founded merely on what can be grasped by the
senses, and then asking whether this bodily nature is ensouled,
and whether a spiritual element is active within it. In dealing with a child
such an attitude is harmful. For in him, far more than in the adult, body, soul
and spirit form a unity. One cannot care first for the health of the child from
the point of view of a merely natural science, and then want to give to the
healthy organism what one regards as proper from the point of view of soul and
spirit. In all that one does to the child and with the child one benefits or
injures his bodily life. In man's earthly life soul and spirit express themselves
through the body. A bodily process is a revelation of soul and spirit. Material science is of necessity
concerned with the body as a physical organism; it does not come to a
comprehension of the whole man. Many feel this while regarding pedagogy, but
fail to see what is needed to-day. They do not say:
pedagogy cannot thrive on material science; let us therefore found our
pedagogic methods out of pedagogic instincts and not out of material science.
But half-consciously they are of this opinion. We may admit this in theory, but in
practice it leads to nothing, for modern humanity has lost the spontaneity of
the life of instinct. To try to-day to build up an instinctive pedagogy on
instincts which are no longer present in man in their original force, would
remain a groping in the dark. We come to see this through anthroposophical
knowledge. We learn to know that the intellectualistic trend in science owes
its existence to a necessary phase in the evolution of mankind. In recent times
man passed out of the period of instinctive life. The intellect became of
predominant significance. Man needed it in order to advance on his evolutionary
path in the right way. It leads him to that degree of consciousness which he
must attain in a certain epoch, just as the individual must acquire particular
capabilities at a particular period of his life. But the instincts are crippled
under the influence of the intellect, and one cannot try to return to the
instinctive life without working against man's evolution. We must accept the
significance of that full consciousness which has been attained through
intellectualism, and — in full consciousness — give to man what instinctive
life can no longer give him. We need for this a
knowledge of soul and spirit which is just as much founded on reality as
is material, intellectualistic science. Anthroposophy strives for just this,
yet it is this that many people shrink from accepting. They learn to know the
way modern science tries to understand man. They feel he cannot be known in this
way, but they will not accept that it is possible to cultivate a new mode of
cognition and — in clarity of consciousness equal to that in which one
penetrates the bodily nature — attain to a knowledge of soul and spirit. So
they want to return to the instincts again in order to understand the child and
train him. But he must go forwards; and there
is no other way than to extend anthropology by acquiring Anthroposophy and
sense knowledge by acquiring spiritual knowledge. We have to learn all over
again. Men are terrified at the complete change of thought required for this.
From unconscious fear they attack Anthroposophy as fantastic, yet it only wants
to proceed in the spiritual domain as soberly and as carefully as material
science in the physical. Let us consider the child. About the
seventh year of life he develops his second teeth. This is not merely the work
of the period of time immediately preceding. It is a process that begins with
embryonic development and only concludes with the second teeth. These forces,
which produce the second teeth at a certain stage of development, were always
active in the child's organism. They do not reveal themselves in this way in
subsequent periods of life. Further teeth formations do not occur. Yet the
forces concerned have not been lost; they continue to work; they have merely
been transformed. They have undergone a metamorphosis. (There are still other
forces in the child's organism which undergo metamorphosis in a similar way.) If we study in this way the
development of the child's organism we discover that these forces are active
before the change of teeth. They are absorbed in the processes of nourishment
and growth. They live in undivided unity with the body, freeing themselves from
it about the seventh year. They live on as soul forces; we find them active in
the older child in feeling and thinking. Anthroposophy shows that an etheric organism permeates the physical organism of man. Up
to the seventh year the whole of this etheric
organism is active in the physical. But now a portion of the etheric organism becomes free from direct activity in the
physical. It acquires a certain independence, becoming
thereby an independent vehicle of the soul life, relatively free from the
physical organism. In earth life, however, soul
experience can only develop with the help of this etheric
organism. Hence the soul is quite embedded in the body before the seventh year.
To be active during this period, it must express itself through the body. The
child can only come into relationship with the outer world when this
relationship takes the form of a stimulus which runs its course within the
body. This can only be the case when the child imitates. Before the change of
teeth the child is a purely imitative being in the widest sense. His training
must consist in this: that those around him perform before him what he is to
imitate. The child's educator should
experience within himself what it is to have the whole etheric
organism within the physical. This gives him knowledge of the child. With
abstract principles alone one can do nothing. Educational practice requires an anthroposophical art of education to work out in detail how
the human being reveals himself as a child. Just as the etheric
organism is embedded in the physical until the change of teeth, so, from the
change of teeth until puberty, there is embedded in the physical and etheric a soul organism, called the astral organism by
Anthroposophy. As a result of this the child develops a life that no longer
expends itself in imitation. But he cannot yet govern his relation to others in
accordance with fully conscious thoughts regulated by intellectual judgment.
This first becomes possible when, at puberty, a part of the soul organism frees
itself from the corresponding part of the etheric
organism. From his seventh to his fourteenth or fifteenth year the child's life
is not mainly determined by his relation to those around him in so far as this
results from his power of judgment. It is the relation which comes through
authority that is important now. This means that, during these years,
the child must look up to someone whose authority he can accept as a matter of
course. His whole education must now be fashioned with reference to this. One
cannot build upon the child's power of intellectual judgment, but one should
perceive clearly that the child wants to accept what is put before him as true,
good and beautiful, because the teacher, whom he takes for his model, regards
it as true, good and beautiful. Moreover the teacher must work in
such a way that he not merely puts before the child the True, the Good and the
Beautiful, but — in a sense — is these. What the teacher is passes over into
the child, not what he teaches. All that is taught should be put before the
child as a concrete ideal. Teaching itself must be a work of art, not a matter
of theory. The case method is based on a
philosophy of professional education which associates knowledge directly with
action (Boehrer, 1995). This philosophy rejects the
doctrine that students should first learn passively, and then, having learned,
should apply knowledge. Instead, the case method is based on the principle that
real education consists of the cumulative and unending acquisition, combination
and reordering of learning experiences. There are two fundamental principles
underpinning the case method. First, the best-learned lessons are the ones that
students teach themselves, through their own struggles. Second, many of the
most useful kinds of understanding and judgement
cannot be taught but must be learned through practical experience. When
instructors assign problems or papers in a course, they are motivated by a
similar concern: by working through the problem set on their own or writing the
paper, students reach a deeper understanding of the concepts and ideas than
they would have if they only read the text or listened passively to lectures.
Case method teaching extends this principle to make preparing for class and the
class session itself an active learning experience for students. By using complex
real-world problems as the focus, it challenges students to learn skills that
will be appropriate to deal with the practical problems that they will face as
economists, civil servants or private managers. Teaching through the case method
allows educators to address specific pedagogical issues and to develop
higher-order skills in students. Velenchik (1995)
highlights four pedagogical issues addressed by the case method: Motivation to learn
theory. In general,
undergraduate economics courses tend to treat applications as secondary to the
exposition of theory. In our teaching we often use examples to illustrate the
application of particular theoretical concepts. However, we tend to use the
example to reinforce the theory, having taught the theory first, rather than
thinking of the theory as a set of tools for answering the question posed by
the application. The focus, therefore, is on the theory itself, and the
application is often perceived as incidental. When students do not understand
the purpose of theory, the process of learning becomes more dry and difficult
than it needs to be, and they often fail to grasp the tools they need. In the
case method, the problem that the students are challenged to solve takes centre
stage. They soon realise that they do not have the
tools and they start looking for the tools. They want to learn theory. Application of
theory. The ultimate goal of
economics education is to enable students to apply economic reasoning to
particular policy issues. The focus is generally as much on the process of
policy analysis as on the specific area of policy. One method for illustrating
the process is through examples related to lectures. However, this is
problematic. The example is often preceded by theory, so that students think of
the application as a use of the theory, rather than seeing the theory as a tool
for dealing with the issues raised by the application. Examples are commonly
selected because they are good illustrations of particular theoretical
concepts, but they do little to help students learn which theories are
appropriate for which kinds of policy problem. On the other hand, the case
method requires the student to identify the theory that best addresses the
economic problem under investigation. Use of evidence. Empirical analysis, guided by theoretical concepts
and analytical tools, is central to many economics modules. Students are often
required to develop an ability to use quantitative evidence. This often
involves a number of tasks, including determining what types of evidence are
relevant measures of particular phenomena, evaluating the credibility of
available information, performing calculations to arrive at appropriate and
useful measures, and finding the best way to convey this information using
tables and graphs. In this respect, although the lecture and example method
usually provides students with some exposure to quantitative information, it
does not require them to do the work themselves. A prepared classroom example
does not provide training in how to select, manipulate and present such
evidence; nor does it help students learn to interpret evidence themselves.
Case studies include raw data that students have to manipulate, represent and
comment on in order to solve the problem. Limitation of
theory. One of the most
difficult aspects of applying economic analysis is
understanding which parts of a question can be answered by economic
analysis, and which are best addressed using other disciplines. In particular,
students need to learn the difference between identifying economic consequences
of a policy choice and considering these decisions in the broader social and
political context in which policy-makers and business leaders find themselves.
It is difficult to use a lecture and example to fulfil
these goals, since classroom examples are often abstracted from their context.
The case method forces students to be confronted with the broader
(non-economic) consequences of economic decisions. The case method can also be used in
a very effective way in order to move students gradually up the cognitive
skills ladder from the low skills levels of knowledge, comprehension and
application to the higher and more desirable skills of analysis, synthesis and
evaluation. This educational taxonomy was originally proposed by Bloom (1956)
and, even if not uncontested, it provides a transparent and structured approach
to the development of students’ skills. The following list describes this
educational taxonomy and then explains how the case method helps in developing
each of the skills. Knowledge. This refers to the student’s ability to remember
previously learned information. It involves the recall of a wide range of
material but all that is required is bringing appropriate information to mind,
not necessarily understanding its meaning. The case method is probably not the
most efficient way to convey knowledge. However, in combination with some
lectures, it can be used to broaden knowledge. Comprehension. This skill is defined as the ability to grasp the
meaning of material and it can be demonstrated by translating material from one
form to another, by interpreting material and by extrapolating information. By
basing knowledge within a real-world context, the case method supports and
facilitates the comprehension of basic knowledge. Application. This is the ability to use learned material in new
and concrete situations. It may include the application of rules, methods,
concepts, principles, law and theories. Through the analysis of policy
decisions or business strategies, students develop an understanding of how
theory is applied in real-world contexts. Analysis. This identifies the ability to break down material
into its component parts so that its organisational
structure may be understood. The process generally includes identification of
the parts, analysis of the relationships among the parts and recognition of the
organisational principles involved. As already
mentioned, analysis is at the centre of the case method. The case studies
require students to break down complex information, establish relationships and
identify issues. Synthesis. This skill refers to the ability to put parts
together to form a new whole. The process may involve, for example, the
production of a unique communication (presentation) or a plan of operations
(research proposal). Case studies foster this skill by requiring students to
identify relevant information, summarise fundamental
concepts and present a concise summary of main events. Evaluation. Critical evaluation is concerned with the ability to
judge the value of material for a given purpose. After having
analysed and synthesised a
particular case, students are required to engage in an evaluation of
alternative policies or strategies available to policy-makers or business
leaders. This can include an evaluation of decisions already taken
against possible alternative solutions. The case method is a rich and
powerful approach to the development of cognitive skills in students. It is
also a flexible approach, in the sense that lecturers can use it in alternative
ways. These are discussed in the next section. Pedagogy the
science of the specially organized, goal-oriented, and systematic molding of a
human being; the science of the content, forms, and methods of upbringing,
education, and instruction. The basic categories of pedagogy are
personality formation, upbringing, education, and instruction. Personality
formation, formerly called upbringing in its broad sense, is the process of
shaping an individual by means of goal-oriented influence (upbringing in the
true sense of the word) and of the varied and often contradictory influences of
the environment. In contemporary foreign pedagogy the first group of influences
is often called intentional upbringing, and the second functional upbringing. In Marxist pedagogy, upbringing is a
key concept referring to the goal-oriented activities of society and family
directed toward forming a fully developed person, chiefly in institutions and
organizations specially created by society. The concept of upbringing generally
comprises intellectual, moral, labor, aesthetic, and
physical upbringing as well as the formation of a world view. However, such
distinctions are largely arbitrary, since upbringing in practice is a single,
integrated process. Education is the process and result of
assimilating a system of knowledge and of developing skills and habits
eventually ensuring a certain level of development of a person’s cognitive
needs and capacities and his ability to perform some kind of practical
activity. A distinction is made between general and specialized education.
General education provides each person with the knowledge, skills, and habits
he needs for overall development. These are the basis for a subsequent
specialized education, whose goal is preparation for professional work. In
level and scope, both general and specialized education may be primary,
secondary, or higher. Polytechnic education is an integral part of general
education. A most important means for effecting
education and upbringing is instruction, the process of transmitting and
assimilating knowledge, skills, and habits and the modes of cognition necessary
for the realization of a continuous educational process. The process of
instruction comprises the two interconnected parts of a single whole: teaching,
the pedagogue’s transmittal of knowledge and his supervision of students’
independent work; and learning, the students’ mastery of a system of knowledge,
skills, and habits. Pedagogy is one of the sciences studying man, human
society, and the conditions of human life; thus, it takes its place alongside
such disciplines as philosophy, ethics, aesthetics, psychology, political
economy, ethics, sociology, history, anatomy, physiology, and medicine. It uses
their hypotheses and research methods, including mathematical statistics and
cybernetics, as well as the results of their empiric research. Structure and
system of pedagogic disciplines. Within the framework of pedagogy are a number of
relatively independent divisions dealing with individual facets of teaching and
upbringing. The development of the goals, tasks, content, principles, methods,
and organization of education and instruction is the province of didactics, or
the theory of education and instruction. The theory and methodology of
upbringing concern themselves with the formation of moral qualities, political
convictions, and aesthetic tastes, as well as with the organization of pupils’
and students’ activities. The discipline of school administration studies all
organizational problems related to the management of public education and to
the network, structure, and management of educational institutions. In order to make use of pedagogical
research and to study pedagogy thoroughly as a discipline, it is necessary to
distinguish the features of upbringing and instruction of groups having
different ages and professional orientations. Examples of these groups are
preschool children; pupils and students in general-education schools,
vocational schools, secondary specialized and higher educational institutions;
and members of the military service. Here, such arbitrary designations as
preschool, school-age, and higher-educational pedagogy are used, and under
study are the organization and the upbringing and instructional methods for a
given contingent of students. The specific pedagogic principles governing each
group are taken into account. Related to pedagogy as such are the
teaching methods for individual disciplines. Defectology
studies the psychophysiological development of
abnormal children and the principles of their upbringing, education, and
instruction. It includes such narrowly specialized branches as the theory and
methods of bringing up, educating, and instructing deaf and hard-of-hearing
children, children who are blind or have poor vision, mentally defective
children, and children with speech defects. Also related to pedagogy is the
history of pedagogy, a discipline that studies the development of the theory
and practice of upbringing, education, and instruction during various
historical periods. Development as a
science. The first attempts
to interpret upbringing in terms of the needs of society were made during the
period when slaveholding states flourished in the During the Middle
Ages, pedagogical views in Pedagogical views of the 14th to
16th centuries reflected both a striving to free human thought from religious
dogma and the revival of interest in man himself and in his everyday work.
These were traits characteristic of the period of feudalism’s decline and the
emergence of capitalist social relations. Writing in diverse
genres, Renaissance humanists such as T. More, T. Campanella,
Erasmus of Rotterdam, F. Rabelais, and M. Montaigne advanced ideas of an
all-around harmonious development of man’s spiritual and physical resources.
They favored a secular education based on the assimilation of the ancient
world’s cultural legacy and on the achievements of science, which was developing
rapidly. The history of pedagogy as an
integrated theory of educating man began at the time of the first bourgeois
revolutions in Beginning with the period of the
English Civil War of the 17th century, two basic trends in the development of
pedagogical thought may be distinguished. The feudal and clerical concept of
upbringing continued to prevail, but at the same time a new, bourgeois
interpretation of upbringing emerged, whose goal was to mold a man of action
and prepare him for his struggle for personal well-being. A clear expression of
the new ideals of upbringing is found in the works of the English Enlightenment
philosopher J. Locke, who stressed the importance of moral and physical
upbringing and originated the utilitarian approach to education and
instruction. Locke’s opposition to the theory of innate ideas was of major
importance. In the 18th century theories of
upbringing developed chiefly within the framework of the Enlightenment. Guided by Locke’s doctrine of the innate equality of man, such
leading French thinkers as C. A. Helvetius, D. Diderot, and J.-J.
Rousseau developed the hypotehsis of the decisive
role of upbringing and environment in personality formation. Diderot, in
particular, considered one of the basic tasks of upbringing to be the
development of a person’s individuality. The French materialists substantiated
and popularized the idea of a practical education that would eventually replace
scholastic education. The greatest contribution to 18th-century pedagogical
thought was made by Rousseau, who originated the concept of a natural, free
upbringing. Rousseau undertook to outline the tasks, content, and methods of
bringing up and instructing children, proceeding from the specific features of
their physical and spiritual development at different stages of growth; he
stressed the need for more active methods of instructing children. His
influence is seen in the democratic plans for reforming public education in Pedagogical thought in the 18th and
19th centuries was influenced by a number of theses of German classical
philosophy as expounded in the works of I. Kant, J. G. Fichte, and G. W. F.
Hegel. The Swiss democratic pedagogue J. H. Pes-talozzi
played an important role in resolving pedagogical problems. He attempted to
construct a theory of upbringing and instruction based on psychological data.
His experience and thoughts dealt with child development during instruction and
upbringing and with vocational instruction and methods of teaching reading,
writing, arithmetic, geography, and other subjects at the elementary level. His
work stimulated the development of the science of upbringing in the first half
of the 19th century. Pestalozzi was the first theoretician of the public school. During the first half of the 19th
century the German pedagogue, psychologist, and philosopher J. F. Herbart
attempted to present pedagogy as a scientific theory based on philosophy and
psychology. In his view, philosophy laid the groundwork for the goals of
upbringing, and psychology permitted us to find the correct ways of attaining
these goals. A number of Herbart’s theses were used in the later development of
pedagogy. These included his views on the role played by interest in instruction,
on the educative nature of instruction, and on the structure of the learning
process. At the same time, however, bourgeois pedagogues assimilated the
conservative aspects of Herbart’s doctrine. These were expressed in his theory
on handling children, which amounted to suppressing the child’s personality by
means of a detailed and fully elaborated system of restrictions and
punishments. The 19th-century German democratic
pedagogue F. A. W. Diesterweg contributed
significantly to pedagogy in general and to didactics in particular. He
maintained that one of the most important factors in upbringing was the
principle of cultural conformity—the taking into account, during the process of
upbringing, of all aspects of the culture, history, and economy characteristic
of a country and its people. Together with the concept of conforming to nature
in upbringing, originated by Comenius, Rousseau, and Pestalozzi though
interpreted differently by each, Diesterweg’s
principle of cultural conformity significantly enriched pedagogy. In the late 19th century the
movement of progressive education arose. Its adherents expressed the interests
of various strata of the bourgeoisie then hostile to one another but united in
their opposition to the proletariat and its ideology. The followers of the
movement also criticized the scholastic content and dogmatic instructional
methods in schools suppressing the personality of pupils and students. The
representatives of such currents of progressive education as the new
upbringing, the labor school, the movement for art training, and the pedagogy
of the personality advocated the free development of each child’s
individuality. These educators wanted to develop new organizational forms and
methods of instruction, to reform curricula, and to place greater emphasis on
upbringing in schools. The ideas of such exponents of progressive education as
J. Dewey, G. Kerschen-steiner, L. Gurlitt,
H. Scharrelmann, O. Decroly,
M. Montes-sori, and A. Ferriиre
dominated bourgeois pedagogy until the mid-20th century and, to an extent, have
been influential to the present time. In Russia during the 16th and 17th
centuries, the old Christian and feudal concept of upbringing as a means of
overcoming man’s original sin and developing feelings of humility, submission, and
religiosity was challenged by expanding humanistic views of man, although often
expressed in concepts and terms of Orthodoxy, and expounded by Simeon Polotskii, Epifanii Slavi-netskii, and the monastic scholars. The first state system of schools
was established in Before the 1860’s, progressive
pedagogical ideas in The development of the emancipation
movement that began in the mid-1850’s engendered a widespread antiserfdom movement in pedagogy. Prominent scholars,
authors, and educators of the time, including N. I. Pirogov,
L. N. Tolstoy, and N. Kh. Vessel’, discussed problems
of upbringing and of the impending school reform. Of central importance were
questions of the purpose of schools, the humanization of upbringing, and
changes to be made in education and teaching methods. Indiscriminate
application of foreign pedagogical theories and educational systems was
attacked, and a movement for the establishment of a national system of
upbringing emerged. All this contributed to pedagogy’s development into an
independent professional discipline. The establishment of pedagogy as a
science in Ushinskii observed the difference between unintentional molding
of human personality by the society and upbringing as a purposeful activity for
the social reproduction of man. He used the phrase “upbringing in the broad and
narrow sense of the word” to define the process. These observations led him to
define the subject of pedagogy and to divide pedagogy into a number of
branches. By taking a many-sided view of man in the light of information
provided by all the sciences studying man and his life, Ushinskii
was able to found the discipline of pedagogical anthropology, which he
considered the science of educating man as he develops, or pedagogy as such. Research into these fundamental
problems provided the basis for a substantiated theory of education and
instruction, which in turn was the basis for the best prerevolutionary
public-school textbooks and for the development of teaching methods. In the
late 19th and early 20th centuries, general problems of pedagogy and didactics
were studied by P. F. Kapterev, V. P. Ostrogor-skii, V. P. Vakhterov,
N. F. Bunakov, I. N. Ul’ianov,
and P. F. Lesgaft and teaching methods by V. Ia. Stoiunin, V. I. Vodovo-zov, and
D. D. Semenov. These fields developed extensively at this time under the
influence of Ushinskii’s ideas and as a result of his
adherents’ work. Ushinskii’s pedagogical ideas also
influenced pedagogic through among other peoples of The turning point in the
establishment and development of a truly scientific system of pedagogy was the
creation of the theory of dialectical and historical materialism by K. Marx and
F. En-gels in the mid-19th century. The founders of scientific Communism stated
that man is essentially the sum of social relations, which he “transfers” to
himself during the process of social and practical activity. They declared that
even while men influence their natural environment and social milieu, they
change their own nature. These discoveries revealed the means and factors
involved in the social molding of the personality. The works of Marx and Engels
disclosed the class character of upbringing in a class society. Their works
examined in general the content and methods of molding a fully and harmoniously
developed person; the tasks, content, and methods of polytechnic education; the
forms and methods of combining instruction with productive work; and the
correlation between family upbringing and that of society. Marx and Engels
developed the theory of Communist education for the new man. They pointed out
that this theory can be realized only after the power of the working class is
established. The basic tenets of the Marxist
doctrine of upbringing were developed and defined concretely by V. I. Lenin,
who maintained that in a socialist society the younger generation should be
inculcated with a materialist world view, Communist convictions, and high moral
qualities. The means for achieving this goal are a broad scientific education
on a polytechnic base, the linking of instruction with productive work, and the
participation of young people in the work of building a new society. Lenin’s
doctrine of socialist culture, enlightenment, and Communist education became
the basis of modern pedagogy. Pedagogy in the The solution of theoretical problems
of Soviet pedagogy dealing with the relationship of pedagogy to other sciences
and with the definition of its subject, tasks, and methods has called for a
critical review of the pedagogical concepts and theories of the past. As early
as the 1920’s, the People’s Commissariat for Education of the RSFSR founded
research institutes in In the second half of the 1920’s
pedagogical research institutes were founded in the The establishment and development of
Soviet pedagogy is linked with the names of such well-known pedagogues as P. P.
Blonskii, A. P. Pinkevich,
B. P. Esipov, M. A. Danilov,
Sh. I. Ganelin, L. V. Zankov,
M. N. Skatkin, I. T. Ogorodnikov,
and S. G. Shapovalenko (didactics); V. A. Sukhomlinskii, I. F. Svadkovskii,
I. A. Kairov, N. K. Goncharov,
E. I. Monoszon, and N. I. Boldyrev
(theory and methods of upbringing); and N. A. Konstantinov,
E. N. Medynskii, V. Z. Smirnov, F. F. Korolev, D. O. Lordkipanidze, I.
K. Kadyrov, M. M. Mekhti-zade,
A. A. Kurbanov, S. Kh. Chavdarov, A. E. Izmailov, and S.
R. Radzhabov (history of pedagogy). In the years of
Soviet power, scholarly editions have been published of the pedagogical works
of many outstanding thinkers of the past who contributed to the founding of
pedagogy, among them Comenius, Diester-weg, Locke,
Pestalozzi, Herbart, Fourier, Owen, Belinskii, Herzen, Chernyshevskii, Dobroliubov, Pisarev, Ushinskii, and Lesgaft. In
addition, such trends of the age of imperialism as modern upbringing, the labor
school, pragmatism, and experimental pedagogy have been critically analyzed.
Textbooks and teaching aids on pedagogy and history, as well as such reference
works as the Pedagogical Encyclopedia (vols. 1–3, 1927–29), the Pedagogical
Dictionary (vols. 1–2, 1960), and the Pedagogical Encyclopedia (vols. 1–4,
1964–68), have helped summarize and systematize the attainments of Soviet
pedagogy. The chief aim of modern research in
Marxist pedagogical science is to find the best ways to mold a fully and
harmoniously developed personality, one which is spiritually rich, highly
moral, and physically perfect. Pedagogy shows how to develop the content of
education and make it correspond to the needs of socialist economy, culture,
and science. The age of the scientific and technical revolution is marked by a
rapid growth of knowledge in all fields of science, requiring a wider scope of
scientific education. Schools must supply this even while their own means and
those of the students remain almost the same. Factors to be taken into account
include the length of the period of study and of the academic day, as well as
the students’ energy and their fatigue factor. Pedagogy develops new principles
and criteria for selecting the content of general education: it studies the
expansion of learning units, the generalization of
knowledge applicable to the needs of general education, the reinforcement of
system and theory in general education, and the consistent implementation of
the polytechnic principle as a leading criterion in the selection of material
for study. Research in the field of instruction
seeks ways to stimulate students and to develop their independence and
initiative as they acquire knowledge. Thus, research is being carried on which
aims to modernize the canonical forms of the lesson by introducing various
types of group and individual student work while retaining the teacher in the
role of leader. Other studies are being conducted that seek to perfect means
and methods of instruction in order to maximize students’ cognitive interests
and abilities and to develop their ability to organize work rationally. An
important trend in pedagogical research is the study of the political,
ideological, and moral upbringing of youth and of inculcating in them a
communist world view. Such research investigates the content and natural laws
of the process of molding communist views and convictions, as well as effective
pedagogical means to ensure the development in young people of communist
consciousness and conduct. The further progress of pedagogy as a science
depends to a great extent on defining more precisely the subject itself and its
categories and terminology, on improving research methods; and on strengthening
ties with other disciplines. Other current topics of pedagogical
research are the history of individual pedagogical problems and their solution,
as well as the origin of various pedagogical concepts, theories, methods, and
ideas. Such an approach makes the history of pedagogy a true history of the
science of upbringing and gives historical research in the field a prognostic
significance. In other socialist countries as
well, much attention is devoted to the study of pedagogy. A number of
pedagogical research institutes have been founded, such as the Contemporary
bourgeois pedagogy. In the
In contemporary bourgeois pedagogy
there is no unity of approach to the basic problems of upbringing, owing to
dependence on different schools of idealist philosophy and on various religious
doctrines. This absence of unity is reflected in the very names of different
pedagogical trends: neopositivism (B. Russell, T. P.
Nunn), existentialist pedagogy (J. P. Sartre, O. F. Boll-now), Catholic or neo-Thomist pedagogy (J. Maritain, F. X. Eggersdorfer),
and evangelical pedagogy (M. Stalmann, K. Schaller).
These are not true schools of pedagogy but the views on education of proponents
of these philosophical and religious doctrines. There is also a tendency to
divide pedagogy into separate, often self-contained disciplines. These include
comparative pedagogy (Y. Bereday, W. Brickman, J. Lauwerys, F. Hilker.
L. Frese), cybernetic pedagogy (F.
von Cube, H. Frank), and group pedagogy (M. Kelber,
E. Hofmann). In contemporary bourgeois pedagogy,
the chief topic studied is didactics. In particular, researchers are trying to
elucidate the psychological mechanisms governing instruction and learning (J.
Bruner, J. Piaget, H. Roth). They are attempting to
adapt education to the needs of each student; the goal of their efforts
approaches individual instruction. To help realize these aims the
audiovisual-aid method has been developed. Programmed instruction, fashionable
in the 1950’s and 1960’s, did not justify the expectations it had raised:
special research conducted in the In many countries, and particularly
in the References 1.
Woolliscroft JO. In: International
handbook of research in medical education. Norman GR, Newble DI, van der Vleuten C, editor. 2.
Lauvеs P, Handal G. Handledning och praktisk
yrkesteori. (Eng title: Supervising and practical
occupational theory) 3.
Bandura A. Social
foundations of thought and action: a social cognitive theory. 4.
Skyvell Nilsson M, Knutsson A,
Samuelsson B, Lцnnroth P, Pilhammar
Andersson E. Lдkares erfarenhetsbaserade kunskap. Delrapport 1, Erfarenhetens professionella uttryck. (Eng title: Expression of professional experience) Gцteborg: Institutionen fцr vеrdvetenskap och hдlsa, Sahlgrenska akademin vid Gцteborgs universitet; 2006. 5.
Weissmann PF, Branch WT, Gracey CF, Haidet P, Frankel RM. Role
modeling humanistic behavior: learning bedside manner from the experts. Academic
Medicine. 2006;81:661–667. doi: 10.1097/01.ACM.0000232423.81299.fe. [PubMed] [Cross
Ref] 6.
Wenestam C-G. In: Discussions on
some educational issues VII, Research Report 175. P K, editor. Department
of Teacher Education, 7.
Ramsden P. Learning to
teach in higher education. 8.
Irby DM.
Teaching and learning in ambulatory care settings: a thematic review of the literature.Academic Medicine. 1995;70:898–931. doi: 10.1097/00001888-199510000-00014. [PubMed][Cross
Ref] 9.
Kilminster SM, Jolly BC. Effective supervision in clinical
practice settings: a literature review.Medical Education. 2000;34:827–840. doi: 10.1046/j.1365-2923.2000.00758.x. [PubMed][Cross
Ref] 10.
Kernan WN, Hershman W, Alper EJ, Lee MY, Viscoli CM,
Perry JR, O'Connor PG. Disagreement between students and preceptors regarding
the value of teaching behaviors for ambulatory care settings. Teaching and
Learning in Medicine. 2008;20:143–150. doi:
10.1080/10401330801991667.[PubMed] [Cross Ref] 11.
Kern DE, Branch
WT Jr, Jackson JL, Brady DW, Feldman MD, Levinson W, Lipkin M Jr. Teaching the psychosocial aspects of care in
the clinical setting: practical recommendations. Academic
Medicine. 2005;80:8–20. doi: 10.1097/00001888-200501000-00006. [PubMed] [Cross
Ref] 12.
Seabrook MA.
Clinical students' initial reports of the educational climate in a single
medical school.Medical Education. 2004;38:659–669. doi: 10.1111/j.1365-2929.2004.01823.x. [PubMed][Cross
Ref] 13.
Wahlqvist M, Skott A, Bjorkelund C, Dahlgren G, Lonka
K, Mattsson B. Impact of medical students'
descriptive evaluations on long-term course development. BMC Medical
Education. 2006;6:24. doi: 10.1186/1472-6920-6-24. [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Cross Ref] 14.
Williams KN, Ramani S, Fraser B, Orlander JD.
Improving bedside teaching: findings from a focus group study of learners. Academic
Medicine. 2008;83:257–264. doi: 10.1097/ACM.0b013e3181637f3e. [PubMed] [Cross Ref] 15.
Sutkin G, Wagner E, Harris I, Schiffer
R. What makes a good clinical teacher in medicine? A review of the literature. Academic
Medicine. 2008;83:452–466. doi: 10.1097/ACM.0b013e31816bee61. [PubMed] [Cross Ref] 16.
Tiberius GR, Sinai
J, Flak AE. In: International
handbook of research in medical education. Norman GR, Newble DI, Vleuten CPMvd, editor. Vol. 2. 17.
Boehler ML, Rogers DA, Schwind CJ, Mayforth R, Quin J, Williams RG, Dunnington G. An investigation of medical student reactions
to feedback: a randomised controlled trial. Medical
Education. 2006;40:746–749. doi: 10.1111/j.1365-2929.2006.02503.x. [PubMed] [Cross
Ref] 18.
Cote L, Leclere H. How clinical teachers perceive the
doctor-patient relationship and themselves as role models. Academic
Medicine. 2000;75:1117–1124. [PubMed] 19.
Gracey CF, Haidet P, Branch WT, Weissmann P, Kern DE, Mitchell G, Frankel R, Inui T. Precepting humanism: strategies for fostering the human
dimensions of care in ambulatory settings. Academic
Medicine. 2005;80:21–28. doi:
10.1097/00001888-200501000-00007.[PubMed] [Cross
Ref] 20.
Ridder JM van de, Stokking KM, McGaghie WC, ten Cate OT. What is
feedback in clinical education? Medical
Education. 2008;42:189–197. doi:
10.1111/j.1365-2923.2008.03078.x.[PubMed] [Cross
Ref] 21.
Wear D, Kokinova M, Keck-McNulty C, Aultman J. Pimping: perspectives of 4th year medical
students. Teaching and
Learning in Medicine. 2005;17:184–191. doi: 10.1207/s15328015tlm1702_14. [PubMed] [Cross Ref] 22.
Heidenreich C, Lye P, Simpson D, Lourich
M. The search for effective and efficient ambulatory teaching methods through
the literature. Pediatrics. 2000;105:231–237. 23.
Hammersley M, Atkinson P. Ethnography:
principles in practice. 3. Milton Park,
Abingdon, Oxon; 24.
MFR. Riktlinjer fцr etisk vдrdering av medicinsk humanforskning:
forskningsetisk policy och organisation i Sverige (Eng title:The
Swedish Research Council's guidelines for the ethical evaluation of medical
research on humans) 25.
Glaser BG,
Strauss 26.
Gutek GL. Philosophical
and ideological perspectives on education. 2. 27.
Dornan T, Boshuizen H, King N, Scherpbier
A. Experience-based learning: a model linking the processes and outcomes of
medical students' workplace learning. Medical
Education.2007;41:84–91. doi: 10.1111/j.1365-2929.2006.02652.x. 28.
Seabrook MA.
Medical teachers' concerns about the clinical teaching context. Medical
Education.2003;37:213–222. doi: 10.1046/j.1365-2923.2003.01437.x.